Monday, August 17, 2009

What is Harm? Guest Post

[Here's some follow-up on the exchange over what counts as harm to sentient creatures, courtesy of my colleague Bob Hockett]:

I’ve been following the recent exchange on the morality of veganism with interest, and thought I might offer my own two cents’ worth. Please pardon if the actual value of this contribution falls below stated par.

For the moment I’ve got three quick comments to offer, two of them fairly narrow in scope, the other a little bit broader. Perhaps there will be more to say later.

The first narrow comment is probably the one most worth making right now. It is that agreement appears very broad on the proposition that it is wrongful to inflict readily avoidable suffering on sentient creatures, and that this is so irrespective of the biological species that those creatures represent. Many who are vegetarian, vegan or veg-symps, in turn, observe among other things that the means by which we “produce” animal products for human (and pets’) consumption do inflict massive such suffering upon nonhuman (and for that matter even human) animals, suffering that could indeed be readily avoided. Were most of us who have tended to consume these products to know about this suffering, and the ways in which it is rendered inevitable by our principal means of “processing” animal products, these same people maintain in turn, we would many of us quickly come to constitute a very large potential market for alternatives. That market would in all likelihood be sufficiently large as to confer scale economies upon the production processes of the mentioned alternatives, and would accordingly afford means not only of ending the massive suffering being experienced even at this moment, but also of satisfying the earlier mentioned “readily avoidable” condition. We could, in other words, in the long run quite inexpensively end this suffering. Inasmuch as this is so, the current suffering is in an important sense gratuitous.

It seems to me that all of the above observations are empirical in character and readily corroborated or falsified. For my part I find many of them corroborated and none of them thus far falsified, and suspect that others who investigate them will find likewise. If that is so, then we already have here the makings of an overlapping consensus sufficient to prompt broad political action directed to bringing urgently needed change to the practices of certain very large industries (beef, poultry, fish, dairy, leather goods, you name it). People of Benthamite, Kantian, Aristotelian, and all manner of other persuasion seem to me very likely to agree that the massive and readily avoidable suffering now underway can and ought to be ended, and to vote and/or agitate accordingly, if only the fact of that suffering and its ready avoidability are brought to their attention.

My second narrow comment is in a certain sense for another day – the day that the just mentioned massive gratuitous suffering is ended and we have the luxury of arguing more precisely and at greater length the specific grounds of our objections to it. But since I have a conception both of myself as living a temporally extended life and of “us” as sharing a yet more extended such life, and since as an academic and all around loudmouth I can’t help but look forward and opine in advance, I’ll hazard a thought or two about the aforementioned more specific grounds.

There are of course multiple possible such grounds and so any reasonably full comment about them is in potential quite broad rather than narrow. I call my next comment narrow, however, because it is directed principally to the place, in the present context, of some arguments made by David Velleman (assuming I have not mangled them) in another context – arguments that certainly bear upon some though not all grounds upon which one might develop or affirm a more detailed ethic concerning the rights or interests of nonhuman creatures.

I take it that Velleman, much of whose work I should say at the outset that I generally admire, figures into the colloquy between Brian and Mike in virtue of observations he makes in the final few pages of his often illuminating article “Well-Being and Time.” (The article in full comprises about thirty pages of journal text.) The bearing of these pages on the present discussion is further drawn out by at least one other of Velleman’s articles of which I’m aware, namely his “Is Motivation Internal to Value?” So I’ll refer to both of these articles below, hoping that I have neither forgotten nor simply failed to notice the special bearing of any others of his articles and monographs on the present discussion.

Here is how Velleman as I understand him enters into the present discussion: He advances two related and, in their place, altogether plausible theses which, when conjoined to a particular proposition about certain nonhuman animals, initially appear to entail that these nonhuman animals’ lives are, qua lives, devoid of value.

The first thesis is a version of what I’ll here call, following Velleman and others, "internalism" about what is good for or valuable to a creature. (Usually the creatures in question are called "persons," and this proves to matter in a way that I’ll presently specify.) The thrust of this rendition of value internalism, as I understand it, is that what is good for or valuable to a creature must be grounded in some way in what the creature cares about or at least could care about on some plausibly idealized conception of that creature. (The importance of caring of course resonates with certain Frankfurtian themes, and the linkages between some conceptions of well-being and idealized caring is impressively explored in Griffin’s 1986 book, with which Velleman is of course thoroughly familiar.) The alternative to this rendition of value internalism, according to Velleman in “Is Motivation Internal?,” taking a cue from Peter Railton, would be an "intolerably alienated" conception of the creature's good. The putative good for the creature must accordingly be able in some way to "engage" that creature if it is to be taken to be a good "for," or valuable “to” that creature.

The second thesis, which I'll call "wholism" about the value of a life and “particularism” about the value of specific events occurring at particular moments of that life, builds and seems to me even to rest upon value internalism of the form just sketched. Succinctly stated, it is the claim that under at least one condition, which I'll presently specify, the value of a creature’s life cannot be composed of or decomposed into the values realized in particular moments of that life. (As in the case of the first thesis, Velleman speaks mainly of “persons” rather than “creatures” here. And once again, presently I’ll say why this is significant and why I generalize the thesis to the case of creatures.) There are accordingly at least two distinct and autonomous species of value associated with the living of a life: synchronic value associated with events that occur at particular moments of a life (as experienced by the liver of that life), and diachronic value (again as experienced by the liver of the life) associated with entire lives of a certain kind – the kind that meets the condition I am to specify. (The conceptual space between these two species of value might be analogized to that between lines or line segments on the one hand and points on the other in geometry. That “disconnect” is part of what brought such puzzlement to the project of “arithmetizing” analysis at the turn of the last century, via the then-seemingly requisite attempts to “build” lines out of points – puzzlement that culminated in the set-theoretic paradoxes.)

Now to that “condition” to which I have alluded: It is that the creature in question possess a conception – or, I suppose one could say in a more venerable idiom, a “representation” – of itself as living a temporally extended “life.” A creature’s meeting this condition not only figures into Velleman’s argument for wholism about the value of a life, but also seems to be at least part of what renders a creature a “person” in the first place for purposes both of the arguments that figure in “Is Motivation Internal?” and “Well-Being and Time.” So I’ll call this the “self-consciously life-living person” condition.

The reason that meeting this condition supports wholism about the value of a person’s life (at least to the liver of that life), I think I am correct in taking Velleman to argue, is that a person’s conception of her own life bears a particular kind of structure – a narratival, or "dramatic" structure. The structured character of a narratival life brings it under a distinct category of value, the wholist one. For in a narratival life it is not the constituent moments, but the “story” that various episodes as interrelated come ultimately to constitute, that yields the value associated with that life by the liver of that life. Within such structures it is not only the benefits and burdens accrued at particular moments, but, among other things, also the orders in which they accrue that bring success, failure, meaning, value, and so on to one’s life. This not unfamiliar take on value in human lives has struck me as plausible and indeed compelling for as long as I’ve been aware of it. But now what about cows?

The reason that wholism about the value of a certain kind of life – that of a person as philosophically understood – undercuts the value of a cow’s life, I take Velleman to argue, is that a cow (as Velleman admits to assuming) simply does not meet the self-consciously life-living person condition. It does not seem to be what Velleman would call a “person” at all. It “cannot conceive of itself as a persisting individual and consequently cannot conceive of itself as enjoying different benefits at different moments during its life,” as he puts it. In consequence, there is no narratival life or, therefore, “whole-life” value for a cow. There is at most only “particular-moment” value. (Those last two are my terms, so please don’t blame Velleman.)

Now, how to assess this argument as an argument to the effect that a cow’s life lacks value qua life? I’ve three reactions, the first of which is merely a reminder: The argument of course does not touch, nor is it meant to touch, the question of whether readily avoided animal suffering matters. So please bear in mind the remarks made above: We are presently discussing only the more particular grounds for deploring and seeking to end massive gratuitous animal suffering, in order that we might begin to work out views as to what more to do or avoid once we have ended the mentioned massive gratuitous suffering. Back, then, to the argument as seen in that light.

Now if I have accurately abbreviated the argument, then it of course depends partly upon the “no self-conscious life-living for cows” assumption. It also depends pretty clearly upon the first thesis that I mentioned – Velleman’s rendition of value internalism (as the second thesis itself – life-value wholism / moment-value particularism – looks to do). And Velleman is explicit about hewing to this rendition of value-internalism in considering the possible value of a cow’s life. “What the cow cannot conceive, it cannot care about,” he observes, “and so a cow cannot care about which sequences of momentary goods it enjoys.” The cow’s caring in this way will of course be relevant to the value of its life only insofar as Velleman’s rendition of value internalism is – forgive me – internal to the conception of value at stake. Is it internal to the conception of value we ought to be employing?

To his credit, Velleman considers several – including weaker – forms of value internalism, with a view to determining whether there might be any rendition that could authorize us to say that a cow might care about its life as distinguished from moments of its life. But in the end no such rendition of value internalism that Velleman considers proves stable. (As it happens I think he’s too quick about one of them, but I don’t want to rely on that so I’ll skip this large question for now.) So Velleman ultimately concludes that “we should refuse to combine” momentary benefits and burdens accruing to cows. Instead we should conclude that “a cow can fare well or ill only at particular moments.”

I believe it is open to us to contest the particular conception of faring well, tied to the species of value internalism at work in Velleman’s argument, upon which Velleman’s conclusion follows; and so I shall do in a moment. But first I want to say a couple of things about the no self-conscious life-living for cows assumption upon which the conclusion also (perhaps less problematically) rests.

I confess to not yet having arrived, or for that matter even having tried to arrive, at any firmly decided view on what manner of self-consciousness or life-consciousness a cow – or many other creatures – might have. And this is partly because the conception of value that I find apt in the present context – a conception quite distinct from Velleman’s – moots the question. I will say however that I am often quite struck by how blithe we sometimes can be in matter-of-factly attributing or denying this or that mental capacity to this or that nonhuman animal. I know that the attribution of this or that kind of mental representation or concept-possession to this or that creature is partly (though I think not wholly) a means of interpreting various movements in which we find the creature – including the human creature – engaged. And I know that there is therefore presumably less reason to attribute some forms of concept-possession, including self-concept-possession, to some creatures than to others. (I have of course assumed that the onus of proof is on the attributor in acknowledging this.) But this is only one of what I’ve a strong suspicion should be many considerations that would properly enter into more fully considered concept- and other capacity-attributions to human and nonhuman creatures alike. And it would be good to see much more reference to such considerations by claimants on all sides of these discussions, at least when they are relying on these attributions or denials. Sherry Colb, incidentally, has accumulated a wealth of information on these matters.

I should add that I have also heard and read sufficiently many denials of various forms of consciousness and other mental capacity to, for example, dogs, the attributions of which forms subsequently turn out to afford the apparently best means of explaining things that my own dog does, to have developed a certain skepticism about these glib denials. I have little doubt, for example, that Atticus, the dog in question, carries something like representations of self and other, and of temporal patterns and continuity, even though I cannot at the moment imagine what would tend to corroborate or falsify a proposition to the effect that he has a narratival sense of his own life in its temporal entirety. But enough of that for now, since again it is first a very large subject to which I cannot do justice in short (or perhaps even long) order, and second, not what I think to be the most decisively contestable feature of Velleman’s reflections as brought to bear on the case of nonhuman creatures. For that feature is, I think, the aptness of value internalism as described by Velleman to the case in question.

Now the kind of “internality” to which one alludes in speaking of the forms of value internalism at work in Velleman’s argument is, I take it, that suggested by such locutions as “the internal point of view.” Value internalism is, if so, a view pursuant to which something is valuable “to” something else only if that something else is itself able, as a creature with affect, to value that thing. But there is of course nothing that requires us to restrict our conception of value to any rendition of internalism as thus understood – or, therefore, to elide without comment from a cow’s life’s not being valued qua temporally extended narratival life by the cow, to the cow’s life’s being devoid of value, simplicitur.

I think that “Well-Being and Time” is perhaps insufficiently attentive for present purposes, in its last few pages – which after all appear to figure as a sort of afterthought to the principal concerns that occupy the first twenty-six pages – to questions of appropriate scope in connection with that to which value is expected to be internal (or is it that which is expected to be internal to value?). It is perfectly intelligible, for example, to say that certain viral infections are bad “for” lizards or wasps, or that vaccinations are good “for” a dog, and that they are in that sense disvaluable or valuable “to” those creatures – by being thus to their natural lives – even when those creatures are not themselves capable from their internal points of view of “disvaluing” or “valuing” the burdens or benefits in question. If there is a conception of a well-formed, properly functioning, healthy or flourishing instance of a particular life form or other type, then there is a conception of what is good for or valuable to the things of that type – a conception that is internal to the type even if not to the consciousness of the instances of that type.

Now the capacity to carry a representation of one’s own narrativally lived life, and the possession of some form of autonomy in conceiving one’s own articulated conception of the good life, and finally, a consequent capacity to “care” about things with a view in particular to their contributions to or detractions from one’s well-lived narratival life, seem pretty clearly to be internal to that form of life known as (philosophical) “personhood.” And for that reason it is hardly surprising – it is altogether fitting – that Velleman’s articles referenced above, which as noted before concern themselves from their outsets with “persons” and frame themselves accordingly, would make use of a species of value internalism to which Frankfurtian care or Railtonian engageability is itself internal – a species of value bound up with the “internal point of view” of a conscious individual. And so those of us who are respectful of persons qua persons will tend to view the value simplicitur or objective value of a life, and the subjective valuation of that life by its liver, as somewhere near full overlap in this, personal, case. At least that will be so insofar as we eschew, as most liberal political philosophers nowadays do, perfectionism of Hurka’s variety. But where the ambit of a creature’s self-awareness or self-representation (if any) falls shorter of the ambit of its full natural life than we find in the case of the (philosophical) person, it seems to me that we cannot legitimately restrict the value of the creature’s life to its own capacity to value that life – at least not without further argument. For the internality involved in value’s being internal can in these cases be plausibly characterized as internality to the species or life form itself about whose instances we are speaking.

Now for my own part, I am inclined to say that value inheres in lives qua lives, narrativally self-represented or otherwise, and that the tendency of most living things to struggle to hold onto their lives is simply one indicator of this. I recognize that there is perhaps something vaguely Platonist (not to say Aristotelian, more on which in a moment) about thinking this way. But I’m not convinced that I’m ultimately any more Plationistic than is, in effect, Velleman. For, after all, even if a person’s fully articulated, internally and autonomously projected lifeplan were cut short by his death in his sleep, and he was not in any sense any longer capable of being aware of the fact, there would be no loss of value, to the now unknowing former-liver, occasioned by the failure of his lifeplan to be realized, it seems to me, unless the conception of value at work in a claim to the contrary was independent of ongoing actual valuation by the life-planner. (I’m of course bracketing third-party valuing both here and in the case of nonhuman creatures.)

So I am going to recommend that we work with a conception of value to which I believe even Velleman himself is at bottom committed. This conception has it that a life is valuable even independently of the capacity of its liver to value it as a life of some more or less specified temporal duration. It is a conception with which I suspect most of us work at least intuitively. And for reasons just indicated I do not believe anything Velleman says undercuts this conception; indeed quite the contrary. I hasten to add, before I proceed to my last comment, that none of this is to say that the values of particular nonhuman creatures’ lives cannot be over-ridden by other values, any more than the value of a self-consciously lived life to its (representative, unimpaired) human liver cannot be over-ridden. It is only to deny the claim that they are altogether devoid of value qua lives as distinguished from moments of lives. It is to claim that all living things are the beneficiaries of defeasible obligations, on the part of those of us who examine our lives with a view to acting upon judgments of value, not to destroy them cavalierly – and that the real question is therefore not whether there are such defeasible obligations, but the conditions under which they are legitimately defeated.

Now, I recognize that there is probably something not only Platonic, but also Aristotelian in spirit in the view I have just begun trying to articulate. Indeed, I would seem to be committing myself to the value of more lives than those even of animals, and perhaps even to the value of “nature” itself. And this takes me to my third and final comment for now.

I recall being quite struck, as a child, by the particular form of disgust – a disgust tinged with sorrow and worry – that I experienced when another child once employed the dead body of a fish as a sort of “ball” of the kind associated with a particular game. I was also quite struck by the strangely lurid, deranged sort of laughter into which he fell as he did so, as though even he was aware at the back of his consciousness that there was something deeply disordered about what he was doing, and was in a sense worried about it. The fish, as I say, was apparently already dead, and so presumably well beyond even momentary experience. Yet it somehow felt as though this creature was in a certain sense being wronged by the child who thus kicked it around, and that the child was in a certain sense wronging himself and others in thus wronging the fish. The fish and the child and perhaps others, or the world of which they were part, or perhaps all of the above, seemed to be treated with a profound disrespect in this happening – desecrated, as it were.

This particular perception of wrong I experienced also seems to me somehow continuous with that which I find myself strongly inclined to attribute to the gratuitous despoliation of anthills and natural environments, and to the cavalier killing of creatures – even hypothetically painless such killing. It seems even to be part of the ground of my disgust with gratuitously inflicted pain itself. Why? I think it has something to do with the awe, the respect, the joyful astonishment that the sheer beauty and complexity of all living things, especially conscious such things, tends to inspire. Even watching an ant colony feels like watching a kind of miracle, let alone squirrels or kittens at play. A fish is so marvelously, as it were painstakingly designed, all in a manner that suits it to flourish in the environment it inhabits, that it is disgusting and seems profoundly wrongful when someone kicks it around like a ball. You needn’t be a creationist or “intelligent design” advocate to find a life and the form it instantiates wonderful, or to find a quite poignant species of value associated with it that does not feel as though it has to have anything to do with your “needs,” y our “interests,” or even your care – even though it happen to speak to some such need, or that you understandably care about it.

It has sometimes been said that ethics and aesthetics are “one,” or that they are at any rate akin. Exceedingly good deeds are often found “beautiful” gestures, justice seems bound up with symmetry (the English word “fair” was used first, I believe, of beautiful faces), and virtues are facets of well crafted characters. I seem also to recall that it has been said, I think by Kant, that the good will is in some other manner associated with a deep sense of “Achtung” – a sort of reverent attention. (It is wonderful that the French counterpart, “attention,” can in the imperative mood mean both attention and waiting. He who says “attendez” says “wait, look!”) I am tempted to say that the value of any creature’s – including the human creature’s – life, and perhaps even part of the profound disvalue of such creatures’ needless sufferings, is deeply rooted in whatever it is that seems so often to elicit this sense of respect from us. Perhaps it is the same ground as that which elicits that “wonder” with which Aristotle said philosophy begins. The faculties of wonder, of respect, and openness to goodness, beauty, and life’s value all seem to me faces of one faculty.

I don’t know yet whether this faculty, when heeded in moments of silent attention, must prompt all to attempt to go vegan, even if it prompts me a growing number of others in that direction. Nor do I know whether it will prompt all, as it seems to be prompting me and as it seems to have prompted others, notably the Australian logician Richard Routley, to make common cause with the “Deep Green” movement. (I do know it will likely not lead me to change my name to “Sylvan,” as Routley did!) But I suspect it will prompt most who will stop for a moment and listen, to be deeply respectful of all living creatures. And I’m sure it will prompt all who take time to learn what we’re doing to millions of nonhuman creatures, to agree this is not duly respectful – just as it is not humane.

Thanks for the exchange and thanks for listening. Maybe more later.

Posted on behalf of Bob Hockett

20 comments:

Brian Leiter said...

Your reconstruction of Velleman's argument seems to me quite fair. I lost you totally however with the paragraph beginning, "Now the capacity to carry a representation...." I take it you are rejecting value internalism, even about what is good for a person?

Here is perhaps a simple way of clarifying what is at stake: on the view you are trying to defend, what is bad about death?

Patrick S. O'Donnell said...

I would have thought the question should be rather what is bad about "killing" non-human animals, not death as such, in which case killing animals to eat them involves a denial of what is good for them, that is, to live their lives as this or that type of animal in realization of what is good *for them* (and as this good consists in their well-being, such welfare need not be conceived soley in conative terms).

Assume, say, that pleasure is one such good as part of the greater good of living the life of a nonhuman animal: in which case, as Richard Kraut says, "the kinds of pleasure that are good for an animal depend on the kind of animal it is." Or the good might consist in living a healthy life as a member of a particular species. To needlessly kill an animal (killing is a prima facie 'bad' so there may be sufficient reasons to override this presumption) is to deprive it of the good for which it suited as an animal of that sort (and as with us, what is good for an animal may not be what the animal in fact wants). Cf. Kraut: "at a high level of generality, there is something that the good of a human child and that of young members of other kinds of species have in common: it is good for them to grow, to develop, to be healthy, and to flourish." If that be true, needlessly killing them (e.g., for dietary let alone gustatory reasons) amounts to a fairly arbitrary of what is good for them.

Patrick S. O'Donnell said...

erratum: "fairly arbitrary denial..."

Patrick S. O'Donnell said...

Upon further thought I wasn't too charitable to Brian: perhaps we might re-phrase his question to ask "What is so bad about a death *from killing* for the non-human animal qua non-human animal?"

Patrick S. O'Donnell said...

Bob,

The paragraph that begins "This particular perception of wrong I experienced also seems to me somehow continuous with..." I found particularly moving and eloquent. Indeed, in conjunction with what you've said about value, it reminds me of Richard W. Taylor's book on "biocentric ethics," Respect for Nature: A Theory of Environmental Ethics 1986). As Taylor writes, "if the animals and plants of the bioculture *were" viewed as having a kind of worth additional to and independent of their usefulness to humans, then the question of how they ought to be treated" would entail certain moral contraints and requirements that entail the sacrifice of at least *some* human interests. Taylor has a nice discussion of what his theory of environmental ethics entails for the "issue of meat-eating versus vegetarianism," and his conclusion is one I think we all could live if not flourish with:

"Even if it became possible for us to devise methods of killing them, as well as ways of treating them while alive, that involved little or no pain, we would still violate a prima facie duty in consuming them. They would still be treated as mere means [i.e., not creatures with inherent worth or value] to our ends and so would be wronged."

All the same, Taylor goes on to discuss the fact that animal suffering does raise important questions in practice if only because

"any form of conscious suffering is an intrinsically bad occurrence in the life of a sentient creature. From the standpoint of the animals involved, a life without such experience is better than a life that includes them. Such a being's good is not fully realized when it is caused to suffer in ways that are not contributory to its overall well-being. We know this in our own case, and must therefore infer that it is so in their case."

Angus said...

Prof. Hockett:

Two worries.

1. I think there's a shift in your "argument from disgust" against the destruction of animals (last four paragraphs of your post), which has potentially troubling implications.

You start out appealing to your intuition that the dead fish - and, mutatis mutandis, other animals - was "in a certain sense being wronged by the child." From there I expected you to say something like "and if the dead fish was wronged by the child, then surely the child would also harm the fish (qua fish) were it bash it around while it was alive; and this regardless of whether the fish feels pain or conceives of itself as a persisting being."

Instead, you go on to hypothesize that "this particular perception of wrong I experienced...seems to me somehow continuous with [your view that it's wrong to stomp on anthills &c. because they are awesomely complex and beautiful]." But if you're right that these two intuitions are explained by your judgment that complex and beautiful things ought to be respected, then there's reason to think your intuition that the dead fish is being wronged is NOT the intuition that the dead fish qua fish is being wronged, but that the dead fish qua complex thing (beautiful even in death) is being wronged.

That, to me, seems a very different sort of reason for denying the permissibility of killing animals than the reason that you ostensibly were aiming to motivate (that the fish qua fish is harmed). In fact the two justifications are in tension. We don't appeal to the beauty and complexity of human beings as a reason not to kill them, and would probably find it off-putting if someone did, precisely because we think humans qua humans have a right to life.

2. You never really address Velleman's (by your own admission plausible) statement that only a being that can perceive of itself as persisting can have a right to life. Instead you help yourself to intuitions from which the impermissibility of killing animals pretty directly follows. In addition to your argument from disgust, your other major argument against Velleman starts from the assumption: "It is perfectly intelligible, for example, to say that certain viral infections are bad “for” lizards or wasps, or that vaccinations are good “for” a dog, and that they are in that sense disvaluable or valuable “to” those creatures – by being thus to their natural lives – even when those creatures are not themselves capable from their internal points of view of “disvaluing” or “valuing” the burdens or benefits in question." Obviously Velleman's wrong if that's true (provided, of course, that the intelligibility of these valuations is grounds for affirming them).

Of course there's nothing per se wrong with trying to confute an argument by appealing to the fact that its conclusion clashes with intuitions. But when the argument's premises seem plausible it is, at least, unsatisfying for you to rest without providing an explanation why the premises' plausibility is only apparent. (And it might be more than that. If it we were content with someone's saying "here are some (pretty non-trivial) intuitions, they clash with X's surprising conclusion, so X's conclusion is false" we'd run the risk that our methodology unduly favors the theoretical status quo.)

Michael C. Dorf said...

I confess to a certain uneasiness about the Aristotelian quality of Bob's argument, perhaps only because of the history of Aristotelian arguments to the effect that, say, it is in the nature of the slave to be enslaved or it is in the nature of farmed animals to be exploited and eaten.

But as Bob himself says, the Aristotelian argument he develops addresses a hypothetical situation. The overlapping consensus he identifies in his first point does nearly all the work for me, as I have been saying now perhaps ad nauseum for the last week or so.

Robert said...

Hello All,

Thanks very much for these very helpful comments and requests for clarification. I'll try to address them later today. Have an eye examination shortly.

Thanks again and more soon,
Bob

酒店ㄚ君姐姐 said...

,,,,,,,,,姐.,,,,,,,,,,,,,,,,,,,,,,,,,,,,,

Robert said...

Hello Again, All,

I'm still planning to address the comments here -- alas, off to another medical appointment this afternoon. Patrick, I'm very appreciative indeed of the references to Kraut and to Taylor. Could you point me to the source of those observations of his that you quote? (I suppose I ought not be surprised that a specialist on the ancients would say things so congenial to my own sensibility, in light of the sort of Aristotelian tone of what I wrote earlier!) Anyway, more soon and thanks again.

Bob

Patrick S. O'Donnell said...

Bob,

First, I hope all is well on the medical front.

The Kraut material is from his recent book, What is Good and Why: The Ethics of Well-Being (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2007). [I bought it after skimming through it and noticing the final chapter was entitled 'The Sovereignty of Good'--I immediately thought of Iris Murdoch's short and deeply moving book by that title and, well....]

All good wishes,
Patrick

Robert said...

Hello Again, All,

Finally a few moments to respond directly to the helpful thoughts and questions here:

First, I think my answer to Brian, if fully elaborated, would run along lines anticipated by those helpfully quoted by Patrick. While I'm still not sufficiently informed, and have still not thought long or well enough, as to feel myself ready as yet to be appropriately "decided" on all of this, I tend at least provisionally to think that we have a generic *concept* of "good," which is then "relativized" or "refracted" into somewhat more specific *conceptions* of "the good for creatures of kind x," where "x" is a variable ranging over different forms of life. That which is characteristic of the ordinary barn owl is internal to "the good of the barn owl." That which is characteristic of dolphins is internal to "the good of the dolphin." And so forth. Different life form, different variation on the good.

The more complex the form of life in question, in turn, the more complex, I reckon, will be that conception of the good -- or of "health," or of "flourishing," or the like -- which corresponds to that form of life. There are presumably more faces of value in a human life than there are in a ground squirrel's life, and surely more than there are in an oyster's life. But there are faces of value, I suspect, in all lives.

How would this more generic rendition of value internalism -- life form as internal to value -- link up with Velleman's form of value internalism -- what V calls "motivation" as internal to value? I think more or less like this: Velleman's form is simply a special case, tailored to the many-layered human "person," of the more general form just roughly indicated. Carrying a representation of oneself as persisting over the course of a narratival life, and "caring" about how that narratival life proceeds, is among those many traits that are characteristic of the human form of life. Hence motivations keyed to such narratival cares are indeed internal to human value. (So I definitely do not reject V's rendition of value internalism.) But other motivations -- e.g., the motivation to flee from the butcher's knife -- also are internal to value in human life, qua biological life as well as qua narratival life, and are internal to value in other living creatures' lives as well.

As for bad in general and the bad of death in particular, it seems to me that these too will vary with the form of life in question, and be more complex according as the creature in question is more complex. To each layer of "good" for a life form, I suppose there probably corresponds some possible bad. A narratival life's being cut short prior to the life plan's fulfillment is of course a bad -- a narratival bad. But so will a biological life's being cut short prior to the lapsing of its characteristic span -- it will be a "biological" bad.

Death occurring prior to the end of that span characteristic of a life form -- prior to the completion of a realistic plan made by a narrativally living person, or prior to the completion of a typical lifespan lived by creatures of a particular species -- seems to me to be something like the limiting case of all disvalue, bad, harm, etc., that might be undergone by a living creature.

One might describe the cow's case in this connection, using Velleman's language, thusly: The cow's motivation to flee the butcher's knife is indeed internal to value (in this case disvalue) as reckoned by the cow. And that is because the cow values its life -- in the manner that cows rather than human persons do.

Brian, please do let me know if this seems unsatisfactory. I'm still thinking these things through and am keen to get things right.

Robert said...

I was unable to post all that I wished in the immediately preceeding post, so here is the carryover:

Patrick, thanks very much again for the thoughts and cites in your coments. Email me some time, OK?

Mike, point well taken on Aristotle and "natural" slavery. I'm no authority on Aristotle, but am tempted to say that he himself might simply not have been sufficiently Aristotelian in some of his judgments. Marx once said he was no Marxist, which was so much the worse for the latter. Keynes said he was no Keynesian, which also was so much the worse for the latter. If Aristotle was no Aristotelian, I suppose it is so much the worse for the former!

Angus, I hope the attempt to respond to Brian above responds to your concerns, and that you'll let me know if it does not. I should have been clearer about the fact that the final paragraphs in my post were not meant so much as argument, as they were the beginnings of a sort of phenomenology of a peculiar sort of moral-cum-aesthetic sensibility that seems to be at work in my poor afflicted consciousness. There seems to me to be some connection between the complexity of various life forms and that sense of "Achtung" they elicit from me. (I am somewhat more fascinated by deer than by oysters, though the latter are pretty cool too.) And that "Achtung," in turn, seems to play some role in prompting me to take seriously the idea that there is value (and not just value for humans) in the lives of life forms that are not human. But I certainly do not want to "help myself" to such intuitions as would-be rebuttals of actual arguments actually made by actual philosophers. I am uncomfortable with the last three pages, on cows, of Velleman's twenty-nine page article devoted principally to persons. But the reasons for (as distinguished from the intensity of) that discomfort are more to be found in the considerations I've elaborated above in attempting to address Brian's query than in my disgust with the fellow who kicked the fish.

Thanks again,

Bob

Robert said...

PS: Patrick, thanks for the good wishes about the medical appointment. As it happens, that appointment occasioned yet more cause for perplexity in connection with the present topic. For I learned that the active ingredient in a particular drug that I must have infused all afternoon-long every six weeks is manufactured in mouse organs. I've been receiving this medication for seven years now and only thgought to inquire about this yesterday. Bloody hell, *now* what am I going to do?

Anybody, help?

Incidentally, I believe that in Europe such drugs are required to be manufactured in synthetic solutions rather than in animal organs. But I'll now have to investigate and determine what to do if this is correct.

Thanks again,

Bob

Patrick S. O'Donnell said...

Bob,

Your posts have inspired me to look with a bit more care at Cora Diamond's work as well as re-visit some things written by Roger Scruton, as they both have things to say that seem to take us in a more fruitful direction than current strategies and debates in the animal ethics and rights literature (Scruton of course defends practices anathema to most vegetarians and all vegans yet there's much food for thought in his reflections). Until now I've been largely content to see a plethora of competing if not contradictory conceptions of how we might better treat non-human animals because they brought much needed philosophical scrutiny and general publicity to the subject. Now that these various theories (of Singer, Regan, Franklin, Francione, Pluhar, et al.) have developed or matured (i.e., exposed to clarification, criticism, etc., leaving us with de facto methodological and theoretical pluralism), together with the fact that (at least as I see it) many of the strictly empirical matters are not as hotly contested as they once were (some even showing evidence of something like consensus), it's easier to take a look at the big picture and see what's missing or perhaps just out of focus, to better assess the virtues and shortcomings of the theories separately and in toto.

How all this ties into "the Good" I'm not quite sure, but there does seem to be something conspicuosly missing from the regnant ethical approaches and theories, if only the fact that they're too strictly or narrowly "ethical" (at least as that has come to be understood in contemporary Anglo-American professional philosophy). I'm not attempting any polemic against "analytic" methods or analytical philosophy (I don't mean, for instance, to give solace to those impatient with the methods and abstractions of philosophy) as both are indispensable to our ends albeit in the sense of "necessary yet not sufficient." At least this is one conclusion I've tentatively drawn from Diamond and Scruton (and in some measure, Mary Midgley, who seems in some quarters unjustly neglected).

And I will be in touch.

All good wishes,
Patrick

kelly said...

放鬆心情自由自在的來一趟花蓮旅遊,可以感受花蓮民宿各種不同的風味,所以來花蓮一定要住花蓮民宿哦!因為可從花蓮民宿主人那裡分享到不一樣的花蓮旅遊的經驗以及品嚐花蓮美食道地的花蓮小吃,所以來花蓮旅遊不一定就要享受花蓮高級餐廳的花蓮美食也可以多試試道地古早味的花蓮美味哦!來花蓮民宿可以放鬆整個心情,來花蓮電腦住宿也可以放空自已,來花蓮也可以了解在地的文化哦!住民宿其實是很輕鬆的,住花蓮民宿其實是很容易,還有就是現在是高油價的時代,還自行開車來花蓮嗎?來花蓮租車會比較輕鬆哦!來花蓮房屋租車會比較省錢哦!或是可以請花蓮計程車帶您包車旅遊喔!!歡迎來住住美麗的花蓮民宿囉!!一定要讓您來花蓮旅遊並且讓您愛上花蓮民宿,還有團購美食好吃的蜂蜜蛋糕、養顏美容的蜂王乳以及花蓮美食喔!!

J&D said...

情趣用品/情趣

正妹視訊/網頁設計/情趣用品

情趣用品/情趣用品/情趣


威而柔/自慰套/自慰套/SM/充氣娃娃/充氣娃娃/潤滑液/飛機杯/按摩棒/跳蛋/性感睡衣/威而柔/自慰套/自慰套/SM/充氣娃娃/充氣娃娃/潤滑液/飛機杯/按摩棒/跳蛋/性感睡衣/

自慰器/自慰器/煙火/影音視訊聊天室

色情遊戲/寄情築園小遊戲/情色文學/一葉情貼圖片區/情人視訊網/辣妹視訊/情色交友/成人論壇/情色論壇/愛情公寓/情色/舊情人/情色貼圖/色情聊天室/色情小說/做愛/做愛影片/性愛/

狗熊克星 said...

這波人妻藝人隆乳當中岳庭是非常成功的一個例子,天生有點雞胸,為了挽救大小奶的窘況,以及順便解決雞胸的困擾,所以才會決定進行隆乳,在和醫師充份的討論之後決定了隆乳手術的流程,這是一個十分成功的手術,若您也想要有美美的胸型歡迎來電洽詢有福囉即可完成最新技術蘿蔔腿手術也可以變成鳥啊卡酷喔讓蘿蔔腿變成有完美比例的腿最新技術可輕鬆達成電波拉皮是利用電波加熱原理可以讓你變年輕電波拉皮是畫時代的科技也是女性朋友的福音



您有需要專業的服務嗎本公司專精於的技術對於網路排名技術的演進無論是排名行銷或是進而到搜尋引情排名的網頁優化這些都是屬於自然搜尋的部份,如果您有這方便的需求可以和我們聯絡現在網路發達與進步使的變的非常的重要沒有排名即沒有曝光即是網路排名的另一個名詞至於排名行銷是什麼呢就是將您的公司網站做網頁優化之後再做搜尋引情的自然搜尋排名到第一頁,本公司專精於seo領域發展出來網路行銷關鍵字排名 SEO服務 網站優化 網站建設 網頁設計 的專業網路行銷公司seo網路行銷策略 搜尋行銷等服務 提供關鍵字網站優化排名..等SEO業務 請來電洽詢麥克先生拍樂得seo提供關鍵字軟體, seo軟體..等服務,關鍵字SEO軟體,又叫關鍵字軟體可輕自已做關鍵字seo排名如果你大馬路上seo因享有

什麼是呢?中文的意思是搜尋引擎最佳化的排名優化也是和seo的意思一樣都是指網路排名我們所提供的是全面性的排名行銷服務,對內幫助您的網站做網頁優化對外做搜尋引情自然搜尋的排名讓你的網站和搜尋引情談戀愛本公司專精於的工作,工程師常常為了做客戶的而忙到三經半夜網路排名的工作真的非常的繁鎖,我們提供完整的排名行銷服務從您公司網站的網頁優化到搜尋引情排名的自然搜尋都是我們所擅長的剛出社會工作的年輕人最大的夢想關鍵字到底是什麼玩意兒呢

gaohui said...

On the other hand,Harley boots ed hardy clothes often is the usual lift-up model with a face Christian audigier shield.One luxury full-faced Harley helmet to look for ed hardy shoes can be the GP Tech Metal Warrior. This Kevlar ed hardy outlet made helmet comes standard considering the ultimate Integrated Ventilation to ed hardy Bikini provide you with oxygen in your ride. And, techniques about fogging ed hardy hats in the shield together with the outdoors, the ed hardy swimsuits helmet will be fog proof. The optimim finish on the helmet guarantees ed hardy clothing no scratches, either. However, ed hardy glasses this amazing ed hardy Jackets tool industry around and may just break your bank! If ed hardyprice is an object, devote all across $70.00 and share with the ed hardy iphone cases conventional stock half helmet. That should as ed hardy dresses a minimum produce a number protection an individual's Harley davidson lower.

喜洋洋 said...

高雄縣徵信商業同業公會
南部徵信聯盟
外遇觀測站
大愛離婚諮詢網
離婚大剖析
大愛徵信有限公司
尋人專家徵信服務網
女人徵信公司
華陀徵信
離婚協助中心
跟蹤蒐證徵信器材網
抓姦觀測
大愛徵信
溫馨徵信
成功徵信社