Tuesday, April 10, 2012

Burkean Constitutionalism

By Mike Dorf

Today I am attending a one-day conference at Columbia Law School on "Burkean Constitutionalism." The conference is being organized by my friends and former colleagues Philip Hamburger and Tom Merrill. In addition to the academic types, Justice Samuel Alito will be joining us for at least some of the discussion. Justice Alito was dubbed the "Burkean Justice" by Adam White (also a conference participant), writing last year in The Weekly Standard. The conference raises at least two key questions: 1) What is Burkean Constitutionalism? and 2) Is it a good idea? In this post, I shall preview my presentation, framed around those questions.

Edmund Burke is sometimes regarded as the father of "classical conservativism," although as a number of people have noted, Burke was actually a Whig, which means that he was by our standards "liberal" or "progressive" in important respects. (Carl Bogus wrote an excellent article, Rescuing Burke, explaining this point.) But no matter. Today "Burkeanism" is simply a signal for something like the following view: Social institutions are highly complex and often reflect the accumulated but tacit wisdom of long experience. Therefore, proposals for rapid, radical change should be met with skepticism, because they will frequently have unintended and undesirable consequences. The French Revolution, which Burke discussed in Reflections on the Revolution in France, is generally taken as the archetype of how disregard for the virtues of gradualism can go awry.

Okay, but what is Burkean constitutionalism? In his catchily titled article, Bork v. Burke, Merrill argued that Burkeanism is a conservative alternative to originalism. There Merrill described Burkeanism as conventionalism, and in his paper for today's conference he expands on that idea in the following way: As a Brit, Merrill notes, Burke was familiar with a small-c constitution, in the sense of long-established practices, but not with what we Yanks have, a capital-C Constitution, in the sense of a written document. Merrill's idea is that, in interpreting the large-C Constitution, Burkean judges and Justices ought to be especially deferential to laws and practices that implement the small-c constitution. In this view, long-established practices should (generally) be upheld, even if they conflict with the original understanding. Merrill suggests several advantages of Burkean constitutionalism over originalism but arguably the central one is that Burkeanism is stable, whereas originalism can be enormously destabilizing.

As Merrill's contrast makes clear, his version of Burkeanism is a position in an intra-conservative debate. Yet a number of liberals have embraced some version of Burkean constitutionalism. The most enthusiastic is probably David Strauss (another conference participant), whose book, The Living Constitution, associates the common law method of constitutional interpretation with Burke. The association works at two levels. First, Strauss argues that the common law method itself is a legitimate form of lawmaking because of its pedigree. Second, Strauss argues that case-by-case gradualism is itself Burkean.Merrill does not accept common-law constitutionalism as a form of Burkeanism, but his objection strikes me as stipulative rather than substantive. Burke did not articulate views about the U.S. Constitution, and so any effort to define Burkean Constitutionalism will necessarily involve some imagination. Merrill and Strauss simply translate Burke to the American context in different ways. It is not obvious that either of them is "right" in any external sense.

Nonetheless, there is a case to be made that Strauss is wrong because he is trying to have his cake and eat it too. Matthew Steilen's review of Strauss's book in Legal Theory makes that case. Strauss wants us to believe that the common law method is conservative (in the Burkean sense) but capable of making important adjustments to protect liberal rights. Yet, Steilen argues, the great common law judges (think Cardozo as the archetype) were always best at disguising important breaks with prior precedent as a form of continuity. The common law method, to produce liberal results, doesn't work the way Strauss says it does--or so Steilen argues.

I think Steilen is onto something but I think Strauss is basically right anyway. Decades of political science literature shows us that the Supreme Court does not venture wildly beyond the center of gravity of political opinion--and so in normal times, the Court will not use its adjudicatory tools to decree radical change. Gradualism really is the order of the day for the Court.

What about the difference in perspective between Merrill and Strauss? A decision can be Burkean in Strauss's sense but not in Merrill's (and vice-versa). Brown v. Board is a good example. Strauss devotes a chapter of The Living Constitution to showing how the Supreme Court developed the principle of Brown over time in a gradualist fashion. So he is right that the decision was Burkean in his sense. But the case was not Burkean in Merrill's sense, because in 1954 Jim Crow was well established in the South. It was part of the small-c constitution in much of the country. And so Merrill's version of Burkeanism is tripped up by the same stumbling block that has undone a couple of generations of originalists: Fairly applied, it produces the wrong result in the most important case of the 20th Century.

So do I cast my lot with Strauss? Yes and no. I think that he provides an excellent descriptive account of the frame in which American courts (especially the Supreme Court) make decisions. One would have to be especially obtuse to deny that American courts apply the common law method in constitutional decision making. But I don't think that gets us very far.In a forthcoming review essay in the Harvard Law Review, I argue that Strauss's book cherry-picks examples of cases with happy endings in an effort to show that the common-law method leads to good results. But the common law method simply is how the courts decide cases, and that leads to lots of bad results as well. What distinguishes the good from the bad results is almost certainly something other than the common law method.

My forthcoming essay also reviews Jack Balkin's recent book, Living Originalism. The essay, not to mention the book, makes a complicated set of moves that I will not attempt to summarize here. Instead, I want to focus briefly on Balkin's tacit Burkeanism. Balkin argues (correctly in my view) that social and political movements are the real drivers of constitutional change over time. The role of the courts is chiefly one of mopping up--of using legal tools to rationalize the change that the People make more directly. Balkin then asks whether the game is worth the candle. If the People ultimately make constitutional law and the Supreme Court is not strongly countermajoritarian, why bother with judicial review at all? Balkin's answer is that judicial review adds another “veto point” at which legal change can be blocked, thereby restraining simple majoritarianism and “creat[ing] a bias toward preserving the constitutional values of the political status quo.”

Balkin here alludes to Burkean virtues of American constitutionalism: Our baroque system of federal lawmaking ensures that the status quo will be preserved, absent the sort of extraordinary effort needed to run the Article I, Sec. 7 gauntlet. For Burkeans who are suspicious of rapid change, our system of federal lawmaking--which effectively requires super-majorities to enact legislation--should be attractive, as it preserves the status quo against change substantially more effectively than, say, English-style parliamentary government, in which the Prime Minister's program will be enacted based on a simple majority in the House of Commons.Balkin is also right that adding judicial review as another veto gate effectively renders the system as a whole still more Burkean--or at least that is its effect when judicial review is invoked to invalidate legislative innovations. When, by contrast, judicial review is used to invalidate old laws (e.g., Brown, Roe, Lawrence v. Texas), it is difficult to characterize the Court's action as adding a "veto gate" for laws (typically state laws) that were enacted decades earlier.

Thus, Burkean constitutionalism--conceptualized as a form of conservatism--ends up being suspicious of just those instances of judicial review that conservatives regard with suspicion, even as conservative Burkean constitutionalists would be willing to license the courts to strike down legislative innovations (like a health-care mandate or, in an earlier era, child labor laws). I cannot say for sure that this is how Professor Merrill himself would apply his version of Burkean constitutionalism, but the logic of his argument points in this direction.To my mind, this invocation of Burke to validate most conservative judicial review while questioning most liberal judicial review would all seem a bit too neat, even if I found the results it produces attractive, which I do not.

Accordingly, count me a dissenter from Burkean constitutionalism. I agree that our constitutional system in general and much of judicial review in particular exhibit Burkean characteristics. That is at best a mixed blessing. Self-consciously working to make judicial review more Burkean would be going too far.


Joe said...

Near the end of this interesting summary, rulings like Roe, Brown and Lawrence are referenced.

Such rulings partially balance off the conservative legislative system in which even arguably out of date laws continue on even if in practice they are carried out in an unprincipled and inequitable way.

Griswold seems of this sort. Judicial review limits outliers and at times serves as a minor nudge.

The Dismal Political Economist said...

Why can’t both Burkean and non-Burkean judicial review exist at the same time in the same place, sort of a quantum concept of the Constitution?

For most of judicial evolution the Burkean concept prevails. For example, the prohibition against cruel and unusual punishment would seem a perfect case for the Burkean world. As the standards relating to punishment evolve, so should the Court decisions on the subject of whether or not certain forms of punishment are in violation of the standard. One feels very strongly that this is what the Founders intended with the language as evolution of punishment standards is something they would have been familiar with.

On the other hand there are situations where the non-Burkean judicial review is required. Brown is the obvious example. The concept of de jure segregation simply could no longer be reconciled with the freedoms enshrined in the Constitution and so it had to end. Griswold is another example. These non-Burkean decisions are not always correct or beneficial. Roe v. Wade was a non-Burkean decision that because it lacked the evolutionary history that a Burkean process would have provided remains highly divisive, as does Bush v. Gore.

The process of judicial evolution is a desirable one, but sometimes the Burkean process is just not feasible. The interesting question is now whether or not the impending decision on the Obama health care law will be Burkean on non-Burkean. A non- Burkean Court is neither liberal or conservative, it is just non-Burkean.

Rose Warissa said...

For most of legal progress the Burkean idea dominates. For example, the prohibition against terrible and uncommon penalties would seem the best situation for the Burkean community. As the factors with regards to penalties progress, so should the Trial choices on the topic of whether or not certain types of penalties are in abuse of the conventional. One seems very highly that this is what the Creators designed with the terminology as progress of penalties requirements is something they would have been acquainted with.Cheap Windows 7 professional Key
Cheap Windows 7 professional product Key
Cheap Windows 7 professional activation Key

Wilder Sheldon said...

For the majority of judicial evolution the Burkean idea prevails. For example, the prohibition toward cruel and unusual punishment would appear a best circumstance to the Burkean world. since the needs relating to punishment evolve, so should the http://www.win7keyshop.com Court choices concerning the subject make any difference of whether or not or not particular types of punishment are in violation using the standard. one feels pretty strongly windows 7 key that this really is what the Founders intended using the language as evolution of punishment needs is some thing they would come going to be common with.

love game said...

The procedure of legal progress is a suitable one,WOW Gold but sometimes the Burkean procedure is just not possible. The exciting concern is now whether or not the upcoming choice on the Obama medical wellness care law will be Burkean on non-Burkean. Sell Rs GoldA non- Burkean Judge is neither generous or traditional, it is just non-Burkean.

Aura Valensia said...

One of the more impressive blogs I’ve seen. Thanks so much for keeping the internet classy for a change. You’ve got style, class, bravado. I mean it. Please keep it up because without the internet is definitely lacking in intelligence
kosmetik online frutablend kaminomoto harga glutera serum korea serum gold produk kecantikan

marly aaran said...

This is cool post and i enjoy to read this post. your blog is fantastic and you have good staff in your blog. nice sharing keep it up.
piedmontreal-estate |

loren Jett said...

Having read this I believed it was rather informative. I appreciate you finding the time and effort to put this informative article together. I once again find myself spending a lot of time both reading and posting comments. But so what, it was still worth it!
www.pgg-blueberg.com |

obat herbal said...

kutilmembandeltumbuhdiorganvital ngerinyakutilyangtumbuhdivagina tipsmenghilangkankutildialatkelamin

wasirdenature said...

penyakit sipilis penyakit sipilis bisa sembuh total penyakit sipilis dan pengobatannya penyakit sipilis raja singa

wasirdenature said...

penyakit sipilis disebabkan oleh bakteri gejala penyakit sipilis raja singa pencegahan penyakit sifilis raja singa ciri ciri penyakit sipilis raja singa

herbal medicine said...

penyakit sipilis penyakit sipilis bisa sembuh total penyakit sipilis dan pengobatannya penyakit sipilis raja singa

herbal medicine said...

penyakit sipilis disebabkan oleh bakteri gejala penyakit sipilis raja singa pencegahan penyakit sifilis raja singa ciri ciri penyakit sipilis raja singa

nimi parker said...

I am really enjoying reading your well written articles. It looks like you spend a lot of effort and time on your blog. I have bookmarked it and I am looking forward to reading new articles.
http://www.weddingpicturesct.com |

lionelmessi10 said...

obat gejala herpes kelamin dan pengobatan herpes kelamin dan cara mengobati kanker payudara dan cara mengobati kanker paru dan cara menyembuhkan kanker dan pengobatan kanker dan pengobatan kanker dari china dan obat kanker serviks dan obat kanker herbal dan obat kanker alami ampuh dan obat kanker ampuh dan obat ampuh kanker usus merupakan solusi pengobatan herbal dari denature indonesia

obat herbal said...

obat kutil kelamin alami obat kencing nanah wanita obat herbal kutil kelamin obat herbal kencing nanah 2 obat herbal kencing nanah obat cairan nanah dari kemaluan obat cairan nanah dari kemaluan obat herbal

obat herbal said...

Obat kencing Nanah De Nature Obat Herbal obat Kutil Kelamincara menyembuhkan wasir alami penyebab wasir atau ambeien dan obat wasir atau ambeien obat wasir ramuan tradisional