By Mike Dorf
Writing in the NY Times Week in Review, Adam Liptak notes that Justice Stevens is the only Protestant on the Supreme Court and that should he be replaced by either Judge Garland or SG Kagan (both Jewish), for the first time in U.S. history, there will be no Protestants on the Court. The article goes on to note a consensus (from which U Chicago's Geoff Stone is portrayed as a rare dissenter) for the proposition that religion is simply not a significant factor in Supreme Court identity politics today. Whereas in the past, Presidents and Senators worried about geographic balance and religious identity in picking Justices, according to this consensus, now they worry about race, sex and ethnicity. I mostly agree with this consensus but I want to register three caveats.
1) While I agree that the selection of an otherwise qualified and ideologically mainstream Protestant, Catholic or Jew would not cause much of a religion-based stir, it's certainly possible that the nomination of a Muslim, Buddhist or Hindu (or Jain, Zoroastrian, Baha'i, etc.) would make waves. At the very least, it would create positive buzz about an historic "first," and there would almost certainly be some backlash. I pretty strongly suspect that the backlash would be at the margins of American politics, but then, as recent events (e.g., calls for secession, nullification, Confederate remembrance) show, those margins are pretty wide. So the short of it is we don't know how irrelevant religion is. We don't even know whether a Mormon nominee would face hostility on that basis. There was talk years ago about the possibility of putting Orrin Hatch on the Supreme Court; most of it did not focus on his religion; but the idea never progressed far enough to test the question. (Speaking of Sen. Hatch, props to him for his gracious remarks about Justice Stevens.)
2) If sectarian affiliation (as among Protestants, Catholics and Jews) is no longer especially salient, religiosity might be. Justices Breyer, Ginsburg and Stevens are quite secular in their outlook and their behavior. For all I know, one or more of them is an atheist. By contrast, the Court's conservative Justices tend to be more religious, both in terms of church attendance and belief. Now of course it's possible to be personally very religious and take a strongly secular view of the law. And I don't think for a minute that any Justice thinks to himself or herself along the following lines: "I'm going to vote this way in that case because that's the result favored by my religious principles." I'm sure they all try to decide cases based on impersonal legal principles. But it would be strange if religiosity played no role in shaping a Justice's overall attitude towards the law. Despite the talk of "calling balls and strikes" or "just following precedent" we seem to accept from SCOTUS nominees at their confirmation hearings, just about everyone expects background--including lots of factors but not excluding religiosity--to influence decision making. It would thus be odd if interest groups, Senators, and even Presidents interested in the likely pattern of future votes of a nominee did not consider religiosity, at least as prima facie evidence of a prospective Justice's future votes.
3) Finally, we might ask about what I shall infelicitously call "religulousness" (with a nod to Bill Maher), by which I mean (as Maher did not), something like "attitude towards religion." Justice William O. Douglas was not, as far as I am aware, an especially religious man. But his opinions about religion manifested a view that it is generally a force for good that should be accommodated. E.g., Zorach v. Clauson ("We are a religious people whose institutions presuppose a Supreme Being.") That did not make him reliably "conservative," even on issues of religion. Thus, Justice Douglas was the lone dissenter from the Court's opinion (written by CJ Earl Warren) upholding a Sunday closing law against an Establishment Clause challenge. See McGowan v. Maryland. But in free exercise cases, his esteem for religion and spirituality led him to an accommodationist position. Obviously, these issues are complicated. I would classify Justice Scalia as "religulous" and Justice Stevens as "irreligulous," but they agreed in the peyote case that the free exercise clause does not require exemptions from generally applicable laws. Their different attitudes towards religion manifest themselves in Establishment Clause cases, where Justice Scalia would permit some church-state intermingling that Justice Stevens would forbid. One could attribute these differences simply to different views about the law, but I suspect that there is also something else going on. In Rawlsian language, the less religulous a Justice is, the more likely he will be to insist on "public reason," i.e., he will be skeptical of asserted moral grounds for government policies that appear to define morality in accordance with traditional religious notions, independent of a narrower notion of the harm principle. Thus, to choose a currently salient example, a religulous Justice would be more likely to accept an asserted government interest in "preserving traditional marriage" as a ground for denying same-sex marriage than would an irreligulous Justice.
To be clear, I am NOT saying that religion, religiosity or religulousness is anything like a perfect proxy for views on any particular legal question or even for broader jurisprudential views. I am instead identifying what I suspect are correlations. Any more definite statement on these matters must await a more rigorous definition of religulousness and empirical study of its effects. (I'm meeting shortly with Jeffrey Segal, uber-Court-number-cruncher; maybe I'll ask him whether there are any data on something like this.)
Subscribe to:
Post Comments (Atom)
6 comments:
"To be clear, I am NOT saying that religion, religiosity or religulousness is anything like a perfect proxy for views on any particular legal question or even for broader jurisprudential views."
I don't think that is right. Let me explain what I mean.
There has, to my knowledge, never been an Openly atheist Justice, certainly not in modern times. Such a Justice's position on sexuality, establishment clause issues and probably abortion, could be predicted to nearly 100% (and we would all be better for it).
The thing on which I think you are actually commenting is that among Justices that are, at least nominally, religious and all judeo-christian, there is insufficient resolving power.
I think that is clearly right, as there are simply no significant differences among these various faiths when it comes to issues that will arise before the court.
In a fantasy land in which, however, there was a 5-person atheist majority, cases involving gay marriage, school prayer, "in God we trust", etc. all become very easy to predict the correct outcome.
On Prawfsblawg, Paul Horwitz comments on a point made in this post: http://tinyurl.com/y3uks4p
Paul cites Yoder
[ http://tinyurl.com/y2yq6oj ]for the proposition that J. Douglas was not consistently accommodating of religion. Yes and no. Douglas's position in Yoder was that because of the potential for conflict between the religious views of parents and children, the Court should not simply accept the claims of the parents as speaking for the children. "Religion is an individual experience," he explained. But even there, Douglas made clear that he disagreed with what would eventually become the Smith rule. He wrote in Yoder: "The Court rightly rejects the notion that actions, even though religiously grounded, are always outside the protection of the Free Exercise Clause of the First Amendment. In so ruling, the Court departs from the teaching of Reynolds v. United States." In other words, Douglas took what goes in the academic literature as an "accommodationist" position, and that is all I meant by using the term in my post.
More broadly, I agree with Paul that Douglas's views, here as elsewhere, were quirky. The consummate rugged invidualist, it's not surprising that his notion of religion would be individual-focused. We might say that he favored protecting the individual exercise of religious rights rather than the institutional prerogatives of religions.
I'm glad to see you taking this issue seriously. Lee Epstein dismissed the lack of a Protestant by saying "we have other forms of diversity today' [although this may have been out of context.] To me it is significant that there may be no Protestants on the court: no more significant than (say) no women, blacks, or hispanics but not necessarily less significant, either
監視器
監視器材
手機訊號強波器
亂剪 雷門刺青
京王監視器 大哥大訊號強波器 網站SEO
Stella亂剪旗艦店
網站排名首頁
mefloquine 250mg
Post a Comment