In his dissent to the Supreme Court’s dismissal
of New York State Rifle & Pistol Association v. City of New York on
grounds of mootness, Justice Alito wrote the following about the merits of the
case: “neither the City, the courts below, nor any of the many amici supporting
the City have shown that municipalities during the founding era prevented gun
owners from taking their guns outside city limits for practice.” After arguing
that the plaintiffs should have won on originalist grounds, Alito then
discussed the city’s justifications for its law (now repealed), finding that
those purposes were constitutionally insufficient. In this post, I want to
focus on Alito’s originalist comments.
First,
it must be said that Justice Alito is no originalist (he spent most of his
discussion of the merits on non-originalist concerns). Alito has expressly teased
other Justices for caring about what the founding fathers who lived so long ago
might or might not have thought about modern problems. In an important case
raising the issue whether the police conducted a Fourth Amendment “search” by
tracking a car through GPS technology, Justice Scalia rhetorically asked
whether the founding fathers would have thought that a constable hiding in the suspect’s
“carriage” was a search. The answer being, of course, yes. Alito responded
sarcastically, “this would have required either a gigantic coach, a very tiny
constable, or both -- not to mention a constable with incredible fortitude and
patience."
Similarly,
at the oral arguments in Brown v. Entertainment
Merchants Ass’n, a case where the Court struck down a California law prohibiting
the sale of violent video games to minors, Alito quipped,
"what Justice Scalia wants to know is what James Madison thought about
video games," and if "he enjoyed them,"
In
both circumstances, Alito was suggesting that the times then and now are
different enough to rule out the importance of silly analogies such as comparing
today’s GPS technology to a constable hiding in the back of a carriage or
between today’s violent video games and any technology available to the Founding
Fathers.
For
similar reasons, originalism is a particularly unhelpful way of analyzing
Second Amendment issues (assuming for sake of argument the provision does
protect an individual right to own guns). This disconnect is important given
how important originalism (or at least originalist rhetoric) seems to be to
Justices Gorsuch, Kavanaugh, and Thomas.
Take
for example the issues raised by New York State Rifle & Pistol Association.
The New York state law now in effect (the statute that mooted the case), according
to the city’s lawyer at oral arguments, “allows gun owners with premises
licenses to transport their guns to rifle ranges and second homes outside the
city as long as the only stops they make along the way are ‘reasonably
necessary.’” Justice Alito believed that this disclaimer was not enough to save
the law’s constitutionality.
What
is really at stake in this case is whether New York City (or the state of New
York) may regulate the movement of handguns through the city’s crowded boroughs absent a certain set of conditions. There is
little or nothing from the world of 1791 that can help us answer this question.
The most common form of originalism
today is “public meaning originalism.” This method does not ask judges to
inquire into the subjective intentions of the people living in 1791 (or 1868). Rather,
judges should try to ascertain the original public meaning of the text. But even
if this task could be accomplished with
any certainty, the proposed answers would be unhelpful for two reasons. First,
like all other constitutional rights, the right to “keep and bear arms” is not
absolute and must be balanced against legitimate, strong, or compelling
governmental concerns depending on the right at issue. There is nothing in the
original public meaning of the Second Amendment that can help judges do that.
Most Second Amendment cases today raise issues that the people living in 1791
did not anticipate in a context they could not have imagined. To say there is
an objective public meaning of the text as applied to these new issues is
nonsense.
More
importantly, advocates of public meaning originalism accept that, even if we
can decipher that meaning as applied to a current problem, if that original
public meaning was based on incorrect facts, or if times have changed
substantially, then judges are not bound by it today. In the words
of Professor Ilan Wurman, who wrote a book summarizing public meaning
originalism, “Originalists recognize that original meaning often requires that
the application of the text evolve as modern circumstances evolve.”
Similarly, Professor Ilya Somin, a self-identifying originalist, has said
that nearly all originalists recognize that originalism “is entirely consistent
with updating the application of its fixed principles in light of new factual
information. Indeed, such updating is often not only permitted, but actually
required by the theory.”
The
issues implicated by New York residents traveling through the population-dense city with handguns by their sides has no
meaningful analogue to the world of 1791. New York has changed substantially
(think Times Square), transport has changed dramatically (horses versus cars
and buses ), and firearms are much different
today. In addition, most people with guns back then were trained to use them
because they were much harder to operate than simply pulling a trigger.
If originalist
judges are allowed, or according to Professor Somin, required, to take into
account changed conditions and new facts when reviewing whether New York State
can limit the transport of guns through New York City, then judges will simply
have to balance gun rights against gun safety in today’s world under current
conditions (which is what Alito did throughout his opinion).
The
myriad issues in the lower courts implicating the Second Amendment also suggest
the utter bankruptcy of an originalist approach to these cases. As I have written
elsewhere,
questions such as where people are allowed to possess guns; how many guns one
person may own; whether all guns are protected or just some guns; whether states
may impose rigorous licensing schemes on gun ownership; and whether automatic
weapons may be regulated differently than other guns are all issues that implicate
facts that have changed dramatically since the founding. Asking what the Second
Amendment’s original public meaning was for these difficult issues does not and
will not help judges resolve these questions.
In his concurring opinion in New York State Rifle & Pistol, Justice Kavanaugh hinted that he does not agree with how lower courts have been handing Second Amendment issues. He said that “the Court should address that issue soon, perhaps in one of the several Second Amendment cases with petitions for certiorari now pending before the Court.” When the Court inevitability hears its next Second Amendment case, it may include some originalist rhetoric in its opinion, but that rhetoric will not be sufficient to resolve the difficult issues raised by the clash of gun rights and community safety. Only a clear-eyed focus on today can lead judges to good resolutions of the hard-balancing acts required by the Second Amendment.
2 comments:
Times Square changed significantly in the last thirty years. The seedy porn vision many have of that area has changed. Also, there was also a significant move to make certain areas much more pedestrian friendly. Plans, perhaps temporary, are in place to block over even more areas from vehicle traffic. It is unclear how this all affects the current question, but it is likely to be somewhat relevant to something (e.g., "reasonable" Fourth Amendment balancing).
I agree, with apologies to Strict Scrutiny Podcast, on a basic level originalism is for suckers. What you are left with are rhetoric and selective usage of original material (the rhetoric is the thing here, it is almost cosplay) that provides a lot of flexibility, but the rhetoric implies it is more restraining than those living constitutionalists who make stuff up. The truth is that all are practicing "constitutionalism" and the originalists do it wrong.
A proper usage of interpretation would mix in some history here including from 1791 or 1868 (as the 2A/14A is involved) but as a starting point. Justice Alito actually usefully cited some in McDonald v. Chicago, including showing how the understanding when the 14A was ratified was different than when the 2A was. An individual rights view is more defensible there (including free blacks having guns to defend their homes) than the original 2A which had a more federalist/state militia function.
Kavanaugh used a recent concurrence to reference stare decisis and this is a basic aspect of the whole thing. Changing times in this context is also reflected in the actual case law since 1868. On this front, personally, I think it does help the argument that there is some constitutional right to possess firearms though that isn't really the issue on the ground. It is proper regulation. Even the dissenters in Heller were willing to grant some right to possess while most states already via their own constitutions did so as well.
Alito is the most conservative ideologue on the Supreme Court but was writing for two originalist justices in that dissent. So, he had to toss that in. He also referenced history when addressing the question of the dual sovereignty issue regarding double jeopardy. Of course, originalism need not lead one to merely conservative results. The professor's favorite modern day justice, Justice Souter, used it at times to help advance positions that liberals share (e.g., separation of church and state; liberal leaning positions of state sovereignty questions).
The issue here is not results per se. We can grant for the sake of argument that the best result here protection of gun rights to some degree. It is an honest accounting. On that front, originalism is for suckers, suckers who self-righteously promote the cause. I appreciate the author's engagement with them.
(Some might think Thomas is the most conservative ideologue, but I use that term advisedly; Thomas might be in some sense of the term, but at times does on principle go places that some conservatives might disagree with. Alito is more likely to advance conservative ends, full stop. I also use "conservative" advisedly. Want to say one of the justices is the most liberal ideologue? Go ahead.)
Post a Comment