by Michael Dorf
In my post last week on the indictment of Rick Perry, I criticized the argument by the Perry camp that the use or threatened use of the governor's veto power for nefarious purposes cannot be the basis for a criminal charge because the state constitution assigns to the governor the power of vetoing legislation. I said that this argument was weak, "at least if not further qualified." I then explained both why the maximalist argument made by Perry is weak and how a more nuanced version of the claim could be stronger. Later in the week, Professor Volokh defended the maximalist view. Some of what he wrote addresses other issues raised by the Perry indictment, but to the extent that Volokh has offered a response to my prior post (which he quotes at length), I am not persuaded.
Volokh argues that the legislature cannot, through ordinary legislation, impose limits on the executive's constitutionally conferred veto power. Before explaining where I think Volokh goes wrong, I should note that although each of us has referred to Texas law, the argument is mostly interesting only insofar as it raises general questions of how executives interact with legislatures. Neither of us is an expert in Texas law, and so it's possible that there are peculiarities of Texas law that support or undermine general arguments that he or I have made. And, as I said in my original post, I don't have a view about whether the case against Perry is weak or strong, all things considered. I understood Professor Volokh to be answering my post in the same spirit -- i.e., discussing how these issues work in general in constitutional systems with separation of powers and in which the head of the executive has veto authority. I shall continue the discussion in the same spirit, making general rather than Texas-specific points, except where otherwise noted.
Volokh offers two related grounds for his conclusion that a governor's exercise of the veto power may not be the basis for a prosecution under the particular statutes he is charged with violating: 1) Ordinary legislation cannot override a constitutional provision, so insofar as the state constitution confers on the governor unfettered discretion to exercise the veto power, that constitutional grant of power takes precedence over any legislation; and 2) A governor's veto acts as a check on the legislature, so it would also violate separation of powers for the legislature to place limits on the governor's exercise of the veto power.
These propositions strike me as sound, so far as they go, but I don't think they go as far as Volokh assumes. So, where do we disagree? The core of our disagreement is over proposition 1, which strikes me as an overstatement. A governor or president has complete discretion to exercise the veto power for good or bad policy reasons, or as part of a log-rolling or horse-trading deal, but that does not mean that he or she can never be held criminally liable--at least absent something more than the constitutional assignment of a veto power--for using that power in other, corrupt ways.
Some constitutions have particular provisions providing partial or even total immunity for acts taken in various official capacities. For example, the Speech or Debate Clause of Article I, Sec. 6 of the U.S. Constitution confers such an immunity on members of Congress. The U.S. Constitution contains no such express immunity for executive actions of the President, although in Nixon v. Fitzgerald the SCOTUS relied (partly) on principles of separation of powers to fashion a judge-made doctrine giving the President absolute immunity against civil suits for acts taken in his official capacity; there may be some similar immunity against criminal charges under the federal Constitution, while the person remains in office; however, the impeachment clause makes clear that after a president is out of office he may be subject to criminal sanctions ("but the Party convicted shall nevertheless be liable and subject to Indictment, Trial, Judgment and Punishment, according to Law").
Does the Texas Constitution provide the Governor with immunity against criminal prosecution either during his tenure in office or permanently? As I've said, I'm not an expert in Texas law, so it's possible, but I doubt it. If there were some such express or judicially implied immunity, wouldn't Perry or his defenders have invoked it? In any event, the key point in my last post and this one is that the argument made thus far-- the one I'm critiquing--doesn't rest on any special immunity from prosecution. The argument asserts that the power to veto--in itself--necessarily entails immunity from criminal prosecution under an ordinary law because such a prosecution would be inconsistent with the constitutional assignment of the veto power to the governor. That's the claim that strikes me as overstated.
To see why, consider an analogous question involving rights. It is conventional to say that there is a First Amendment right to burn a flag, per Texas v. Johnson. But it does not follow that someone exercising that right is immune from prosecution for other crimes he commits while happening to burn a flag. If Shmonson used a burning American flag to deliberately set fire to his neighbor's house, he could be prosecuted for arson. If Gronson used a burning American flag to torch his own failing candy store to collect the insurance money, he could be prosecuted for fraud.
Professor Volokh attempts to show that a governor is immune from prosecution for exercising the veto power by giving a number of examples in which the legislature specifically outlaws particular uses of the veto power. Yet his examples are plainly irrelevant to the question of whether the governor can be prosecuted under a general statute when the governor happens to violate that general statute by exercising the veto power. They are like the Texas law that specifically targeted flag desecreation in Texas v. Johnson, not like the arson law or the fraud law.
Volokh does give one hypothetical example in which a governor is prosecuted under a general statute, but it's a peculiar one. Here's his best example:
Say that a governor vetoes a bill appropriating money for some public health measure. Someone dies, allegedly because of the veto (i.e., the person wouldn’t have died had the measure been funded). A prosecutor then charges the governor with “depraved heart” murder, meaning (roughly) that the governor acted despite his knowledge that there was a very grave and unjustified risk that his veto would cause death. Or perhaps the prosecutor charges the governor with negligent manslaughter, meaning (roughly) that the governor was grossly negligent in vetoing the law.I agree with Volokh's intuition that charging the governor with murder or manslaughter in this example would violate the best conception of separation of powers, but not with his conclusion. For one thing, given the libertarian cast of American criminal law, in this context the veto looks like a non-culpable failure to rescue rather than an affirmative act. Moreover, the particular consequences here are inextricably tied up in the governor's policy judgment about whether the public health measure is wise. Presumably the proponents of the health measure argue that absent the measure, people would die, whereas opponents argue either that they wouldn't or that if they do, that's unfortunate but that funding the measure would have other harmful consequences, such as raising taxes, increasing the deficit, etc. Volokh's example really only shows that under the best conception of separation of powers, a governor cannot be prosecuted for the foreseeable consequences of a questionable or even bad policy decision.
But that is not enough. My claim, and presumably the claim of the prosecutor in the Perry case, is not that every time a governor vetoes a law he can be prosecuted for doing so. I am simply denying the Perry camp's equally sweeping contrary claim, namely that a governor can never be prosecuted for exercising the veto power. Even one example of a circumstance in which separation of powers is not offended by prosecuting a governor for his exercise of the veto power would suffice to rebut the maximalist view of Perry's defenders. And we already have one: bribery. As I noted in the earlier post, a governor who vetoes a bill as part of a quid pro quo for a a bribe can be prosecuted for bribery, notwithstanding the fact that the governor has unfettered discretion to make a good or bad policy choice in deciding whether to sign or veto a law.
Volokh does not deny that a governor could be prosecuted for bribery in connection with the veto power, but instead argues that bribery is somehow unique--an exception that proves the supposed rule that a governor cannot be prosecuted for the exercise of the veto power. He attempts to distinguish bribery from all other crimes in three ways. Let's consider them in turn.
1) Volokh cites the 1972 SCOTUS decision in United States v. Brewster, which said that the federal statutory crime of bribery consists in taking the bribe, regardless of "performance of the illegal promise." That's true. It's even possible to read Brewster as relying on a principle of constitutional avoidance for that reading of the statute--although it would be very odd for the Court to apply constitutional avoidance to make it easier to convict a criminal defendant. But let's suppose that we read Brewster for all it is worth. It would mean that the federal Constitution requires that, as applied to members of Congress, the crime of bribery must refer only to the acceptance of a bribe, not the performance of the act for which the bribe is paid. But only for members of Congress, because the constitutional question in Brewster was whether the crime of bribery violated the Speech & Debate Clause, which, as I noted above, is a special immunity for legislators. It is not a general entailment of separation of powers, so it does not apply to the federal executive, much less to executives in all governments with separation of powers.
2) Volokh next says that "there is a special provision of the Texas Constitution that expressly forbids accepting a bribe by an official (including the governor), and authorizes criminal punishment for such behavior." I think Volokh means by this to suggest that, in the absence of this special provision, separation of powers would forbid bribery prosecutions of the Texas governor for the exercise of the veto power. Yet (other than the addition of a line-item veto), the veto provision of the Texas Constitution is very similar to its federal counterpart, which does not need a "special provision" to authorize bribery prosecutions. How do I know the federal veto clause does not create the need for such a special provision? Because the impeachment clause recognizes that the President and other officials may be impeached (and later prosecuted) for "Treason, Bribery, or other High Crimes or Misdemeanors" without specially enumerating what those sundry other crimes are.
As for the Texas Constitution, I'm not sure what "special provision" Volokh is referring to, but the portion of the Texas Constitution setting out the executive powers contains no reference to bribery. There is a general provision of the Texas Constitution that forbids someone who obtained his office via bribery from continuing in office, but that's not at issue with respect to Governor Perry. His case would appear to be governed by another provision in the same Article of the state Constitution obligating the legislature to enact laws that "exclude from office persons who have been convicted of bribery, perjury, forgery, or other high crimes." The reference to unspecified other crimes strongly implies that the background assumption is that gubernatorial misconduct--whether in the use of the veto or some other way--is subject to prosecution, regardless of whether it takes the form of taking bribes or something else. Far from showing the uniqueness of bribery, this "special provision" shows that bribery is merely one of a large class of crimes for which governors can be prosecuted as a consequence of their abuse of power.
3) Volokh then adds that "the risk of prosecution for bribery is far less of a deterrent to a veto (assuming the governor hasn’t been bribed) than the risk of prosecution for violating [other laws], precisely because a prosecution for bribery has to show an agreement to take a bribe — not just a supposedly improper intent behind the veto." This seems to me both wrong and irrelevant.
It's wrong because sophisticated corrupt government officials have ways of taking bribes that are proved in much the same way as other kinds of corruption charges. Unless they are idiots, corrupt government officials do not receive checks with "bribe" written in the memo section; they do not even usually receive bags of small unmarked bills; they typically take otherwise legal campaign contributions in exchange for otherwise legal conduct; or they funnel money through intermediaries. Thus, prosecuting such an official for accepting bribery involves the same sort of evidence as is needed when prosecuting an official for other forms of corruption in which intent is critical. The current corruption prosecution of former Virginia Governor Bob McDonnell makes this point pretty clearly: it is not disputed that McDonnell and his wife took gifts from Johnnie R. Williams; the sticking point is why, just as it would be if the question were improper use of the veto power.
Moreover, even if Volokh were right that proof that a governor illegally took a bribe in exchange for a veto would be more concrete than proof that a governor committed some other crime by exercising his veto power, so what? That would simply mean that, other things being equal, it would be easier for governors to get away with committing one kind of crime than another. It would not mean that the exercise of the veto power is immune to prosecution for all crimes other than bribery.
Accordingly, I think Volokh's efforts to distinguish bribery are wholly unavailing. Still, it is worth considering why he tries so hard to distinguish bribery. He apparently shares my strong intuition that a governor who took a bribe to veto (or to sign) legislation should be subject to criminal punishment for that offense, and that to preserve his separation-of-powers theory he therefore needs some way to show that bribery is unique--that no other offenses may be committed in the exercise of the veto power. That the effort is unavailing is important, but the fact that he makes the effort at all is revealing.
I'll offer one more example of a crime at the federal level that undermines the strong separation-of-powers claim. Consider treason. (Spoiler alert!): Imagine a scenario based on The Manchurian Candidate or Homeland if Brody had become president and remained loyal to his former captors: U.S. intelligence learns of a foreign terrorist plot that would exploit a key vulnerability in domestic defenses; Congress acts swiftly to pass a bill appropriating funds for an emergency fix; but the President, secretly acting on behalf of the terrorists, allows the bill to sit on his desk for nine days, and then vetoes it, during which time the devastating terrorist attack occurs. Isn't this a pretty clear case of Presidential treason via the veto power?
Note that the two examples I've given--treason and bribery--are the two expressly enumerated grounds for impeachment of the President, and both are crimes that can be committed through the exercise of the veto power. There is nothing in the text or structure of the Constitution that would lead to a different result for the other, unnamed high crimes and misdemeanors for which a president can be impeached and subsequently prosecuted. Nor is there anything in the general principle of separation of powers that would lead to the conclusion that treason and bribery are unique in this regard.
Is it possible that a court might nonetheless construe the veto power of the Texas governor in the maximalist fashion I have criticized? Sure. And it's also possible that one or more of the Texas charges will be held inapplicable to Perry's alleged conduct on purely statutory grounds, or that he might be acquitted on the facts. But nothing I've seen thus far from Professor Volokh or anyone else supports the broad claim that a purely discretionary power to veto on policy grounds implies immunity from criminal prosecution for the exercise of the veto power on corrupt grounds.
16 comments:
Re: Federal impeachment clause:
"but the Party convicted shall nevertheless be liable and subject to Indictment, Trial, Judgment and Punishment, according to Law."
What if the Party is NOT convicted?
Shag: There is a robust debate about this and related questions. My tentative view is that the impeachment clause is best read as requiring that a sitting official be impeached and removed before being subject to criminal punishment, OR that his or her term in office end. E.g., Bud McFarlane was never convicted by the Senate because he resigned, but then he was prosecuted in court. Even someone who is impeached but not convicted by the Senate can perhaps be charged criminally once out of office. It seems to me that the Senate can have perfectly legitimate reasons for not convicting, even though the party is guilty. Clinton may well be a good example. I think the mostly Democratic Senators who "acquitted" Clinton did so on the ground that in their view what he did was not a high Crime or misdemeanor within the meaning of the impeachment clause. But once his Term was over I think perhaps he could have been prosecuted for "low" crimes.
You heavily rely on the fact that use of the veto (and the threat of the veto) is being prosecuted under a "general" statute. But constitutionally protected conduct typically retains that status even where proscribed under a general statute, *so long as* the conduct itself is the *only* thing triggering the statute. See, e.g., Hustler v. Falwell (can't punish satire under general non-speech tort of IIED); Cohen v. California (can't punish political protest under general non-speech crime of breach of the peace); compare your hypos (where a burning flag is used to destroy or obtain other people's property). Here, as previously discussed, the only thing allegedly triggering the general statute is the constitutionally protected veto and the constitutionally protected threat of veto.
Relatedly, I don't understand your distinction of Volokh's "veto as depraved heart murder" hypo. Where does the constitution, or even general separation-of-powers principles, draw a distinction between vetoes for bad policy reasons and vetoes for corrupt motives? Even setting aside the fact that one could easily tweak Volokh's hypo to make a "bad policy reason" sound like "a corrupt motive" (e.g., a veto with the *intent* of causing death), the more fundamental objection is that the distinction you're drawing is invented out of whole cloth. The reason that "corruption" is generally punishable is not because of some arbitrary decision among motives for legislative acts, but rather because corruption generally involves unprotected conduct *distinct* from the constitutionally protected legislative act (e.g., receipt of the bribe). Here, though, no such distinct unprotected conduct exists.
As Mr. Dorf points out, he and Mr. Volokh agree that a veto in connection with a bribe is indeed a criminal act regardless of the fact that the veto itself may be authorized by law. The reason is that there is a quid pro quo associated with the veto. The veto in the case of bribery is not the result of disagreement by the Governor of the policy supported by the expenditure, but is motivated by financial gain on the part of the Governor (gain from either not vetoing funding supported by the person offering the bribe or gain from vetoing funding that the person offering the bribe does not want to occur).
If one extends this principle to the situation involving Gov. Perry it is clear that the motivation for his veto is not disagreement with policy, a proper exercise of veto power. Instead his veto is extortion, the threat of financial harm against a party if they do not act in a way that they would not act absent the extortion. (Do what I want and you get funding; don’t do what I want and I will remove your funding.) Mr. Perry apparently had no legal way to remove the targeted individual from office, so he resorted to financial coercion in the form of a veto. (The proper course would have been to seek authority from the legislature to remove the person from office).
This may or may not be criminal activity. Suppose for example that it was the legislature that conditioned funding for the governmental unit on the resignation of an individual. Would this be criminal, probably not. But it certainly a possibility that extortion by the Governor was criminal and akin to bribery, and to say that under no circumstances could it be criminal activity is too extreme, just as saying that it is always criminal activity is too extreme.
Point, set and match to Mr. Dorf.
I'm mostly going to leave the comments section to the commenters, but I just want to respond to one point made by Hashim because it seems to come up regularly: the notion that taking a bribe involves a crime "distinct" from exercising the veto (or whatever). This strikes me as simply wrong: As I note in the post, sophisticated corrupt officials take bribes by engaging in conduct that is otherwise perfectly lawful, such as taking campaign contributions. What makes it an illegal BRIBE rather than a legal GIFT is that it is connected to an agreement to use another otherwise lawful power for an illicit purpose. The same is true for other corruption offenses. I have now said that as clearly as I can. I'll just leave it there.
There was a debate touching upon Shag's question at Balkanization.
Federal judges are now subject to criminal punishment first. Since we are going beyond POTUS to Bud McFarlane, is that wrong or are judges different from an "official"?
The overall discussion is interesting and I think Dorf has the best of it here on points -- EV's person dying hypo, e.g., is as noted a real reach.
I've never said that bribery involve a "crime" distinct from the veto. What I've repeatedly and clearly said is that it involves "conduct" distinct from the veto -- namely, an agreement along with receipt of money. That is not true here -- the *only conduct* involved is the veto and the threat to veto, *both* of which are constitutionally protected.
Okay, breaking my own plan:
1) The demand for a resignation is also separate conduct;
and
2) In my treason hypo, the only conduct is the veto, but I still think it's treason.
Demand for resignation is still constitutionally protected speech. Not true of an agreement to receive money in return for official acts.
As for treason, even assuming treason could occur based *solely* on the executive's *motives* in engaging in official action *without* (as in your hypo) any agreement with the enemy -- and that's far from obvious -- treason is separately proscribed in the constitution, and thus an internal constraint on the executive's constitutional prerogatives.
1. I thought you libertarians believed that politicians taking money is also protected speech.
2. Other high crimes and misdemeanors too.
Now I'm really done
Giving money to politicians, without more, is indeed protected expressive conduct. But giving money to politicans *pursuant to a quid pro quod agreement* is unprotected bribery. As Volokh and I have both pointed out several times now, the unprotected element of bribery is *the agreement*. Although such an agreement may involve speech, proscribing such agreements doesn't violate the 1A any more than does the general crime of conspiracy or the specific crime of price-fixing. And thus any speech involved with bribery is obviously distinguishable from speech that merely "threatens" to engage in constitutionally protected conduct.
"High crimes and misdemeanors" are the grounds for impeachment. So yes, if the legislature tried to impeach, they could assert that "high crimes and misdemeanors" were an inherent constraint on the veto power. But this isn't an impeachment; rather, it's a prosecution under a general criminal statute that has no special constitutional imprimatur. (Not to mention that there's no evidence anywhere that the exercise of the veto with "corrupt" motive alone rises to the level of a "high crime or misdemeanor" warranting impeachment.)
1623It is entirely possible that two separate acts, each of which is legal, when put together result in conduct which is illegal.
For example: Vetoing appropriations is legal in Texas. Soliciting campaign contributions is legal in Texas. But vetoing an appropriation solely on the basis that the individual benefiting from the appropriation failed to make a campaign contribution when asked to do so is surely illegal or at least subject to indictment and trial. Similarly here, vetoing appropriations is legal; asking for the resignation of an official who otherwise cannot be removed is legal. But conditioning the veto on the resignation of an official may well be illegal extortion or coercion.
I fail to see why this is such a difficult concept for anyone to grasp.
I'm not understanding the Volokh-Hashim line here. How about a more outlandish hypo? Suppose that the Governor at the veto ceremony knows that her veto pen is motion-sensitive in a way that will trigger an explosion, killing hundreds of innocent people, if she uses the pen to sign the document. For the Governor to sign such-and-such document IS to veto. The conduct that triggers the relevant (murder?) statute is the signing. Ergo, what triggers the relevant statute is the veto. Surely an exercise of the veto power that IS an unjustified killing is not constitutionally protected. What am I missing?
not be the basis for a prosecution under the particular statutes he is charged with violating: 1) Ordinary legislation cannot override a constitutional provision, so insofar as the state constitution confers on the governor unfettered discretion to exercise the veto fifa 15 coins 英雄联盟代练 Elo Boost
針對馬英九台中援交總統定調要求核四應該續建魚訊論壇,同時將在22日晚間約砲社團與國民黨立委進行溝通外送茶莊,國民黨立委丁守中表示約砲網站,他會參加此場溝通會,摸摸茶因為他希望馬總統在核四案中「不要先有定見」,按摩個人工作室他強調,先完工後再來測試有沒有問題,兼職援這是諫言的漢語詞典解釋援交妹:諫言(jiàn yán),1.規勸的話。規勸的話。援交妹《周書·馮景傳》高雄援交:“ 寶夤 敗後, 台北援交景 還 洛 。朝廷先聞 一夜情景 有諫言,故免之。” 範文瀾 蔡美彪 等《中國通史》外送茶第四編第一章第一節台北援交:“諫院設知院官,應召女對朝政得失、炮友大臣以緻百官援交日記的過錯一夜情援交
一夜情援交金錢豹 夜總會擁有,應召女金錢豹大舞廳,外送茶莊金錢豹大酒店,金錢豹理容KTV援魚, 金錢豹 大舞廳,外送茶坊誠徵:舞廳小姐,伴唱小姐,援交一夜情金錢豹酒店工作,日保薪5000-10000,(外加小費自得約砲), 外送茶坊免CALL客,免拼酒,免出場,茶訊大舞廳打工,叫小姐酒店兼差兼職,自由班,沒經驗, 援-交line金錢豹 一夜情留言板都歡迎!魚訊金錢豹酒店應徵援魚
Post a Comment