by Sherry F. Colb
In my Verdict column for this week, I discuss a decision by the U.S. Court of Appeals for the Fifth Circuit holding a Mississippi abortion law unconstitutional, as applied. The law at issue, like an increasing number of state laws, requires that doctors who provide abortions must have admitting privileges at a local hospital. The doctors at the one existing abortion clinic in Mississippi attempted to acquire admitting privileges at seven local hospitals, but all requests were denied, expressly because of the doctors' participation in abortion services.
The Fifth Circuit held that the law in question, given the circumstances, effectively eliminated abortion services from the state of Mississippi and thereby imposed an undue burden on the right to terminate a pregnancy. My column analyzes the unusually fact-specific nature of the ruling and why it needed to be that way.
In this post, I want to turn from the subject of abortion to the subject of animal rights. What is the connection, you ask? One connection is that Mike Dorf and I are currently working on a book -- tentatively titled Beating Hearts -- about the animal rights and anti-abortion movements. The book addresses substantive arguments that find expression in both pro-animal-rights and pro-fetal-rights camps as well as some of the philosophical and strategic challenges that similarly confront the two movements. One strategic challenge is whether to embrace legislative reforms that regulate the targeted behavior (whether animal exploitation or abortion) and thereby potentially imply that the activity is not itself inherently objectionable, if proposed guidelines are merely followed.
In the context of animal rights, an example of such legislative reform would be a law that provided that laying hens must be kept in a barn rather than in a cage. A proponent of animal rights -- one who believes that breeding birds who produce more than fifteen times the normal number of eggs annually (250-300 versus 10-15 in a closely related non-domesticated bird) in order to take their eggs away and ultimately to kill them when they stop laying those eggs (while killing all of the male "layers" because they produce no eggs) amounts to unjustified violence and cruelty to animals.
When someone who believes in animal rights advocates for a different sort of "housing" for such birds, the advocate could be misunderstood by the public as condoning the farming of birds, so long as they are kept in a barn while they are being exploited and prior to being slaughtered, rather than in cages. The advocate might respond that less torture is better than more torture and that the difference is what motivates the advocacy. Opponents, in turn, could reply that the public responds to such "reforms" by believing (without foundation) that buying eggs is now justified and that "even the animal rights people" at [name your organization] think so." Furthermore, as investigations of "cage free" facilities and other "high welfare" operations reveal, the realities of "humane" farming are routinely no better than the "factory" alternative.
In the abortion context, a regulation might say that "abortion is legal if the doctor performing the procedure has admitting privileges at a local hospital." Such a regulation does not prohibit abortion and might therefore lead an observer to conclude that abortion is fine so long as the providers have some level of access to local hospitals. A supporter of this regulation might respond that such regulations are quite effective at reducing the number of abortions women have, because many hospitals refuse to grant admitting privileges to doctors who perform the procedure, and fetal lives are therefore spared. As a matter of messaging, moreover, pro-life organizations can and do dispel any doubts about their bottom-line position on abortion by saying such things as "we oppose all abortion and believe that abortion is murder from the moment of conception."
The realities on the ground are quite different for people who oppose animal exploitation from what they are for people who oppose abortion, as Mike and I explore in our book, so one might believe that strategies should properly differ for the two movements.
Another sort of issue that arises in both the animal rights and pro-life movements is what sorts of arguments are appropriate and convincing. In the case of abortion, some of the arguments made about late-term abortions might undermine the case for prohibiting early abortion. Emphasizing the horror that accompanies the dismemberment of a 26-week-old fetus that already appears to be sentient may, by negative implication, reduce moral discomfort around earlier abortions of plainly insensate embryos and fetuses. For this reason, some people in the pro-life movement find partial-birth abortion legislation pointless and counterproductive to their mission.
In the animal rights movement, one of the points we make in favor of veganism is that by consuming the products of animal exploitation and slaughter, we solicit additional acts of violence against animals, thereby bringing about physical and emotional agony to innocent sentient beings. Animal rights advocates typically object both to the infliction of suffering on animals (for the purpose of using those animals) and to the killing of animals (for the same purpose -- or because keeping them alive for further exploitation is no longer economically sound).
Some people outside the animal rights movement agree that inflicting suffering on animals is wrong but challenge the notion that killing animals in order to exploit them is necessarily morally objectionable. Their premise is that if one could kill an animal for consumption without inflicting any distress or pain upon that animal, then the killing would not violate the interests of the animal. This is actually a position held by Peter Singer, the Princeton philosopher who authored Animal Liberation. Singer rejects the view that killing farmed animals is wrong, provided that the killing is truly painless.
In an opinion piece in the New York Times, one writer suggests, in line with this thinking, that consuming animals is morally distinct from atrocities against humans, because animals could -- at least in theory -- be raised and slaughtered without suffering any pain or distress. The writer, Rhys Southan, acknowledges that in the real world of animal farming -- even the "high welfare" sector -- animals actually suffer a great deal, in part because babies are taken from their mothers (as is inherent in the dairy industry) and in part because animals are mutilated (branded, castrated, etc.) without anasthesia as part of "raising" them for slaughter. There is far more suffering implicated in creating (and therefore in consuming) animal products than Southan articulates, but even he effectively concedes that "pain free" animal exploitation (and therefore consumption) is, for the moment, a fantasy.
In his column, Southan cites Epicurus for the proposition that death is not a harm to the one who dies, because once someone is dead, that individual no longer exists to experience the putative harm. As Southan undoubtedly knows, though, Epicurus makes this point about humans. Mike and I address the argument that death is not a harm and that painless killing is therefore morally permissible in our book, and I discuss it as well in one of the chapters of Mind If I Order the Cheeseburger? And Other Questions People Ask Vegans, a chapter entitled "What About Plants?". For purposes of the Times opinion piece, however, suffice it to say that if Southan embraces Epicurus's view and infers permission to "painlessly" slaughter animals, then he should -- by his own logic -- infer permission to "painlessly" slaughter humans as well.
For now, however, let me leave this point behind. I will, for purposes of argument, assume a premise that I in fact reject -- that painlessly killing (an animal or a human) is morally unobjectionable. If this is true, what follows from it? It follows from this premise (one that I, just to be clear, find offensive and utterly reject) that if one were to consume the corpse of a slaughtered animal (for example, a puppy or a calf) who had been killed without experiencing any anxiety or pain, one would be doing nothing wrong. Likewise, as Southan implies at the end of his piece, one could also consume (or create gloves out of) the remains of a slaughtered human without committing any moral wrong, so long as the human never saw it coming and suffered no pain or anxiety.
Southan asserts that in theory, one could raise and slaughter animals for food without causing the animals pain or distress. This is true, just as it is equally true that one, in theory, could raise and slaughter humans for food without causing the humans pain or distress. This would especially be true in the case of a human who is either too young to understand complex human communication (through which she might learn of her fate) or a human who suffers from intellectual disabilities that prevent such understanding in adulthood. Under Southan's argument, then, there would be nothing wrong with murdering a happy, intellectually disabled human being, so long as one made sure to sneak up on the person in the middle of the night and cause no suffering in the process.
After accepting this (dubious) premise, what follows? Though Southan does not say so explicitly, he strongly implies (in part by identifying himself as a "former vegan" in his byline) that what follows is that it is morally unobjectionable to consume animal products. Why does that follow? Because even though animals who are raised and slaughtered for consumption in fact suffer tremendous pain, anxiety, and loss during their short lives, as Southan concedes, one could imagine an animal being slaughtered for consumption without the corresponding suffering. In other words, the fact that one can imagine painless exploitation and slaughter is -- on Southan's theory -- enough to make it acceptable to consume the products of painful exploitation and slaughter. Got that?
I would not spend so much time on this rather bizarre argument if this were the first time I encountered it. I would then conclude that Southan is simply confused and move on to other, better thought out, writings. The problem is that I have heard this line of argument before.
In one context, a woman who calls herself an "ethical vegetarian" and is otherwise extremely intelligent insisted to me that consuming eggs is morally acceptable (and totally different from consuming flesh) because the production of eggs need not involve any killing. (By contrast to Rhys Southan, this woman does not appear to regard killing as harmless). I expressed disagreement with her claim, because in the actual world we inhabit, the production of eggs always involves killing. The male layer-breed chicks are, in fact, killed shortly after hatching, because they do not serve the purpose of an egg-laying operation, since they cannot lay eggs.
The woman responded that one could, in theory, take care of all of the male "layers" and permit them to live out their lives rather than killing them. I pointed out that such a practice would be economically ruinous for anyone hoping to earn rather than to lose money selling eggs and that, given the number of male layer chicks killed every year (260 million in the U.S. alone), there would not be enough space on planet earth to allow them to live out their lives other than in horrendously crowded conditions. This might be why, I suggested, there are exactly zero egg-laying operations in which the males are permitted to live out their lives.
When people purchase "back yard" hens, the curiously absent males will have all been thrown into a meat grinder or other such device to make fertilizer the day on which they hatched. Buying eggs (or egg-laying hens for one's backyard) is inextricably tied to that practice.
What I said did not seem to phase the "ethical vegetarian," however, because in theory, one could imagine consuming eggs without killing any male layers. That is apparently enough, from her perspective, to justify consuming eggs in the real world, where male layers are always killed as part of the process.
Ordinarily, as I said, I would not feel the need to respond to such an argument, any more than I would feel the need to respond to the argument "but I had a dream in which an angel said that I should eat eggs." However, because I have now heard the argument twice, I will make an attempt to say something in response, in the hope that people who believe it has some plausibility to it might think twice the next time they encounter it.
Let us take a context outside of the animal rights (and abortion) areas, where controversy is less likely. Say I learn that all chairs coming from the Sandusky Chair Company were made by child slaves who were beaten and forced to work for twenty hour stretches. I happen to like Sandusky chairs, though, because they are very comfortable.
It is undoubtedly true that chairs could, in theory, be made without violently abusing enslaved children. In fact, not only could they be made that way but some chairs actually are made without such violence. Does this fact mean that I can go ahead and buy Sandusky chairs with a clear conscience? In other words, does the fact that one could in theory create a chair without beating child slaves translate into moral permission for me to go ahead and pay the Sandusky Chair Company for chairs that they do create by beating child slaves?
Some purchasers of Sandusky chairs might be ignorant about what is involved in creating those chairs and might therefore be innocent of the violence and cruelty that they are paying for. This is true, but once the reality is brought to their attention, they are no longer ignorant. And in the case of animal agriculture, it is becoming increasingly difficult to remain completely ignorant about the profound violence involved in creating every type of animal product, including (especially) products like chickens' eggs and cows' milk, which visit a special level of hell on the females of those species. And the "ethical vegetarian" of whom I spoke earlier is herself quite knowledgeable about the real world of eggs and dairy, even those that supply supposedly "humane and sustainable" farmers' markets.
Ultimately, then, I must conclude that the "it could be done ethically in theory" argument is not really an argument at all but simply a (rather transparent) rationalization. And I say this as someone who takes seriously the many common objections to veganism in Mind If Order the Cheeseburger? And Other Questions People Ask Vegans. I would say that if something could be ethical in theory but is in fact unethical in practice, then that means that one is under an obligation, absent some truly compelling need, to avoid supporting that something unless and until the fantasy/theory becomes a reality. Though imagination can yield many wonderful things, it cannot justify behavior that is, in reality, unjustifiable.
Subscribe to:
Post Comments (Atom)
10 comments:
I thoroughly object to most of the assertions made in your segue between abortion rights and animal rights activism. (except paragraph 8.)
With the exception of bans on partial-birth abortion, abortion activists have thoroughly rejected the concept of legislative reforms that in practice regulate the targeted behavior. They may pay lip-service to this concept when speaking on the legislative record, but public comments are always clear: the "regulatory" laws they pass are squarely targeted at either closing abortion clinics or in some way harming their women patients.
The two most obvious examples from recent time are requiring admitting privileges and requiring "on-label" use of RU-486. Requiring admitting privileges is about closing abortion clinics, not ensuring that the procedure is safe or humane. Similarly, requiring on-label use of RU-486 is about subjecting abortion patients to unnecessary cost and inconvenience, and involves requiring something that no current medical practitioner considers to be medically sound.
Equivalent actions to these by animal rights activists would be requiring all egg farms to also grow an acre of corn per hen, or requiring those raising cows to carry their food in horse-drawn wagons, rather than gasoline-powered trucks.
In general, animal-rights activists have taken the tack you describe, looking for ways to reduce animal suffering rather than to use regulation to put farmers out of business. While I'm sure this doesn't fully accomplish the goals intended, it also has the advantage of respecting those with different views, finding common ground rather than removing the freedom of others to do something the activists disagree with. This also has the tendency to slowly move community views in the desired direction, rather than simply polarizing them.
It isn't clear whether the reason for the different methods is really a result of differences in view or other practical realities, but they are dramatically different strategies, even if the former is pretending to be the latter.
As for the rest of the discussion, my view (and I suspect many people's view) is not that "inflicting suffering on animals is wrong" but that "inflicting unreasonable suffering on animals is wrong." At that point, it digresses into a discussion of reasonableness that isn't possible to go into here, and makes the rest of the post moot when subjected to my personal views.
Unless you are against, e.g., prisons, you are not totally against human suffering either.
You are against "unreasonable" suffering of humans.
I have my doubts that pro-choice Colb and Dorf are unaware of the general trend of those who support TRAP laws etc. But, the differences in intent is useful to cite.
There is a way to go about this discussion as a thought experiment. Those who support animal welfare laws do have different views - some, e.g., accept some suffering to animals, but think some suffering is gratuitous. They can join with those who wish animals weren't raised for food etc. to pass some of these animal welfare laws.
There are some mixture in the abortion context too -- there is a range of those against abortion, many accept it should be legal, but are conflicted and are okay with certain troublesome limits. Different limits there might be somewhat different (e.g., forced ultrasounds are very well wrong, but they are different from denial of privileges).
The thought experiment also can compare what anti-abortion choice advocates and vegans would do given the limitations of a society that is far from their position.
Finally, it can address vegans who also are in some way concerned about abortion, especially later in term, and wish to promote "life" in all ways, including animal and embryonic/fetal life.
Prof. Colb does say:
"The realities on the ground are quite different for people who oppose animal exploitation from what they are for people who oppose abortion, as Mike and I explore in our book, so one might believe that strategies should properly differ for the two movements."
I can't fully state all of the shades of my views, but suffice to say, I am somewhat wary about some of these columns and discussions. But, it provides a well argued discussion all the same. The book sounds like that -- a mixture of "uh ..." and "hmmm" etc.
Greg, et. al., who propose the "unreasonable suffering" standard,
I assume the cruelty you are willing to sustain for the purpose of eating and wearing animals you would find objectionable if it were instead done for the human pleasure of watching an animal slaughtered? Just assume everything is the same as it is now, but instead of eating or wearing the animal, you just are entertained by watching the animal slaughtered (after which you have no interest in its parts).
If my assumption above is true, can you meaningfully distinguish the entertainment value of watching a cow killed from the entertainment value of eating a hamburger?
Joe: I agree that I'm not stating anything Ms. Colb doesn't already know. I more feel like she's straining too hard to draw a parallel that simply isn't there than she is unaware of things as they actually are.
I intentionally left my statements in generalizations for a number of reasons, some of which are the ones you cite, particularly from the animal welfare side. I felt it better to praise generally good citizenship than to point to a few potential problem areas or to try to speculate what would happen if things weren't the way they are.
Paul: You ask an interesting question.
I'm not sure I accept your equating of eating animals for food as "entertainment" but it isn't an unreasonable way of looking at it either. There are benefits of eating meat, but most of them fall under the guise that meat eating provides a "dietary shorthand" for meeting dietary needs without being careful about ensuring that you get them from other sources. Even this is largely cultural.
In the case of a cow, I would argue that the trade-off is between the value of eating beef in a variety of forms for 3-6 months, wearing leather shoes, having leather seats in my car, not to mention gelatin, glue, and any number of other products made from cow. In my view, this is a pretty big pay-off for the death of a single animal, and some of these are not simply entertainment products. Artificial leather simply isn't the same as natural leather in ways that matter beyond "entertainment."
Fowl are perhaps a different story. Simply because they are smaller, the payoff for killing a single chicken is a few meals and some animal by-products that are much more difficult to use than those produced by the beef industry. Still, even then some effort is made to use these.
The interesting result of this is that if you assume that the life of all animals is equivalent, then it is less moral to each chicken than to eat beef, because the body count is higher when eating chicken.
This is an interesting thought experiment.
Ultimately, I end up rejecting your premise. While I appreciate the reasons for it, I refuse to equate eating meat with entertainment. If food choices constitute entertainment then it naturally follows that any action not strictly necessary for survival is entertainment.
I like living in a house. I prefer it immensely to sleeping with a blanket under the stars, particularly when it is raining. The house I live in is quite modest by modern standards. Still, lumber to build that house contributed to deforestation. Furthermore, the land that house stands on no longer contains the animal diversity that it once did, due simply to my presence and the land taken up by my house's foundation. I still don't classify the house as an entertainment expense, nor do I consider the deaths of some animals as a result of its construction to be killing animals for entertainment.
Killing animals to eat them is not significantly morally different from driving animals from their homes in order to build my shelter that is larger than absolutely necessary. The scale may be different, but that again produces a reasonableness discussion, not a bright-line rule.
I don't think anti-abortion advocacy and nonhuman rights advocacy can be easily compared. Abortion opponents might speak about suffering or unnecessary death, but they also focus on abortion being used as birth control, defying the will of a supreme (paternal) deity to give and take life as ordained, and usually it is in no way linked to other human rights issues like capital punishment or war. To oppose abortion does not usually require any kind of personal sacrifice or moral action. In animal rights-especially as defined by veganism, it is focused on personal moral action (avoiding products that come from exploitation). If animal rights was truly comparable to anti-abortionists, then we would see AR advocates seeking to outlaw the sale of vegetarian or vegan products because it encourages people to enjoy the taste of flesh or dairy (as we see anti-abortion advocates seeking to limit access to contraception-i.e. Planned Parenthood). There are some vegans who have implied that fake meat and dairy products are morally wrong for vegans to use, but even the most extreme have not sought to legislate them out of stores.
Another difference is practical:
To be in a position to seek an abortion only requires pregnancy--very easy to set up and achieve, farm exploitation on the other hand requires immense resources to construct and maintain it (domestic animals to breed, water and food to feed them, buildings, government money to subsidize it--slaughter wildlife called pests etc). In other words, abortion is more "naturally occurring" than farm exploitation (and this despite the claims we hear that meat eating is sanctions by a supreme deity while abortion isn't!).
Southan's argument is really just window dressing--the core issue (which he admitted to me was a serious problem for nonvegans) is the false belief in human supremacy. This is like the belief in racial or religious supremacy used to defend slavery--the myth believer says human suffering and death is "different," in other words, humans are better. This claim of superior worth, like a claim of superior worth based on race or gender or religion, is entirely founded on biased personal opinion. Whether its "mind," a soul, Divine or Biological favoritism, contractualism, Might Makes Right etc any and all criteria used to support human superiority either cannot be shown to be possessed equally by all humans or lacking in all nonhumans--and regardless, Nature and/or invisible mute deities cannot be proven to care. The greatest debunker of human superiority claims? Human behaviour. Just check today's news and read about all the acts of humans exploiting other humans according to a belief they are superior in value. So if you want human rights you really have to accept the logic and fairness of nonhuman rights. If you don’t, then you leave a loophole that allows racial and religious supremacists to justify their exploitation of humans, using the same belief system that a human supremacist uses to deny nonhuman rights--one based entirely on biased personal opinions (even when they deny it to be so). Humans are the only ones shown to need or use moral codes, nonhumans cannot be proven to need or use them. To deny them beneficiary status because they cannot understand human morality is like demanding an armless person catch drowning swimmers and when they fail-punish them as callous. We call that unfair. Also unfair is any suggestion that the inability to be perfect in morality invalidates all moral concepts. I.e. if you cannot be perfect in dealing with insects or plants that this somehow justifies farms and vivisection labs. When you are aware of the human supremacy myth and the double standards arising from it, you would see that if we were fair, it would mean that since we cant stop random homicides or child abuse (or abortion if you like), it means that concentration camps and warfare are justified too. This is how I frame animal rights and veganism.
高雄縣徵信商業同業公會
南部徵信聯盟
外遇觀測站
大愛離婚諮詢網
離婚大剖析
大愛徵信有限公司
尋人專家徵信服務網
女人徵信公司
華陀徵信
離婚協助中心
跟蹤蒐證徵信器材網
抓姦觀測
大愛徵信
溫馨徵信
成功徵信社
movements is what sorts of arguments are appropriate and convincing. In the case of abortion, some of the arguments made about late-term abortions might undermine the case for prohibiting early abortion. Emphasizing the horror that accompanies the dismemberment of a 26-week-old fetus that already appears to be sentient maybuy cheap fifa 15 coins LOL Boosting
thanks so much i like very so much your post
حلى الاوريو الفطر الهندي صور تورته حلى قهوه طريقة عمل السينابون طريقة عمل بلح الشام بيتزا هت كيكة الزبادي حلا سهل صور كيك عجينة العشر دقائق
Just want to thank the author very much for this article and express my total agreement with all the positions she discussed.
Post a Comment