By Mike Dorf
In my latest FindLaw column and my post on Monday, I took issue with the framing of the relevance of Romer v. Evans as standing for the proposition that taking a right away is necessarily constitutionally problematic. Of course, during the oral argument in Perry, the panel understood that rights can sometimes be taken away. Judge Reinhardt made the point in his colloquy with attorney Charles Cooper. The judge acknowledged that in general the people of a state can amend their constitution, even taking away rights, but he went on to suggest that this power is limited by Romer, and one question in Perry is whether that limit applies in this context. As I explained Monday, I don't think Romer stands for the proposition that some rights can't be taken away. I won't rehash that argument today. Instead, I want to ask whether, quite apart from Romer, there are rights that can't be taken away. Think of today's post as addressing the question of whether there is a constitutional endowment effect.
It strikes me as implausible to say that there are any rights that can never be taken away. To be sure, some constitutions make it impossible to take a right away. For example, Article 79 of the German Basic Law forbids any amendment that would change the protection afforded for human dignity (Article 1) or the democratic character of the German state (Article 20). But the U.S. Constitution does not have this kind of permanent entrenchment, except with respect to the Senate (a provision also paralleled by the German Constitution). So when I say that I'm interested in whether there are limits on taking away rights I mean I'm interested in whether there are rights such that it is harder to take them away than never to grant them in the first place; I'm not asking whether there are rights that are impossible to take away once granted.
Framed that way, we can connect this question to the broader question of when it should be hard to change the law. Typically, interests in reliance, planning, and stability for its own sake are invoked to justify rules--such as the presumptive weight given to stare decisis--that entrench the status quo. None of this quite maps directly onto our question. For one thing, stare decisis applies across doctrines, not just to rights. For another, horizontal stare decisis is a doctrine about a court preserving its own previous judicial decisions. Here I'm interested in the question of whether a legislature or court should be externally bound for having "gratuitously" recognized some right.
The set of constitutional doctrines that seem most promising here are procedural due process and Takings law. Under procedural due process, for example, a state that need not grant welfare benefits at all cannot grant them through legislation but then deny them to a particular individual without affording adequate procedures. But this is not a perfect analogy because the legislature retains the power to abolish the entitlement wholesale. Takings is a somewhat better fit: Where government has created a property interest, it cannot destroy it--even with full procedural protection or even by legislation--without paying just compensation. Thus, limitations on regulatory takings do seem like a pretty good example of rights that once granted, cannot be taken away (absent something dramatic like a constitutional amendment).
More broadly, I would note that a certain view of originalism conceptualizes rights in general as reflecting the you-can't-take-it-away impulse. In particular, Justice Scalia contends (at pages 40-41 of Common Law Courts in a Civil Law System: The Role of United States Federal Courts in Interpreting the Constitution and Laws, in A MATTER OF INTERPRETATION: FEDERAL COURTS AND THE LAW (1997)) that the whole point of a Constitution is to prevent backsliding on rights (and other matters). Of course, Scalia's view--and on this point I think his view is widespread--would say that only those rights that are entrenched through some extraordinary process of adoption (such as the super-majoritarian process for Constitution making and Constitution amending) get anti-backsliding protection. So I doubt that he would endorse the can't-take-rights-away approach with respect to a right that was only recognized by a (controversial) judicial decision, as in California with respect to same-sex marriage. But there is nonetheless a sense in which everybody endorses the notion that the whole idea of rights is that they can't be taken away without something extra beyond what is normally required to change the law.
Subscribe to:
Post Comments (Atom)
9 comments:
So what does Casey represent? Did the court carelessly backslide when issuing the updated (and deferential) undue burden standard? Or did the existing right under Roe make even that difficult? I'm guessing it's the latter -- because it would have been easier to uphold those PA laws in the absence of any previously defined core right.
Off-topic but still related to Perry v. Schwarzenegger:
In your Findlaw column, you wrote: "But alternatively, a finding that no one has standing to defend Prop. 8 on appeal could be read to entail that no one had standing to defend it at trial--in which case the appeals court might have to vacate the entire opinion by the district court."
Why wouldn't a consequence of this alternative be summary judgment for the plaintiffs, given that the proper defendants of Prop. 8 -- i.e., certain state officials -- chose not to defend the ballot measure in district court (the disquiet of the Ninth Circuit panel respecting tacitly nullified referenda notwithstanding)?
Under common law jurisprudence a "right" cannot be "taken away" except by way of deprivation under criminal due process, the "activity" deemed by way of conclusive presumption as "legal" vested use,the only other exception being compensatory for "public USE", not purpose. The Constitution, despite the harpings of "modern" jurisprudence, upholds common law in this respect, reinforcing what came afterwards in the declaration of our Federal Bill of Rights, the safeguard of the "people" against intrusive government, whether "state" or "united states".
Eric: The Casey joint opinion (a majority opinion on this point) relies on the can't-take-it-away logic for upholding what it terms the core of Roe, although the joint opinion (a plurality only in this other regard) somewhat undermines that logic in cutting back outside the "core."
David: I tend to agree with you but some scholars have advanced decent arguments for the view that in the absence of any defense, there was no concrete case. My own view is that if there's no appellate standing, the district court judgment stands as a default against the non-defending govt defendants, but it has no application beyond the particular plaintiffs.
thanks so much for that great blog and thanks also for accepting my links thanks
طريقة عمل الدونات طريقة عمل البان كيك طريقة عمل الكنافة طريقة عمل البسبوسة طريقة عمل الكيك طريقة عمل عجينة البيتزا فوائد القرفه
thanks so much i like very so much your post
حلى الاوريو الفطر الهندي صور تورته حلى قهوه طريقة عمل السينابون طريقة عمل بلح الشام بيتزا هت كيكة الزبادي حلا سهل صور كيك عجينة العشر دقائق
bahayakutilyangtumbuhdipenis obatmerontokkankutildipenis menghilangkankutilyangtumbuhdivagina
cara mengobati penyakit sipilis ataupengobatan herbal gonore penis sakit dan nyeri saat kencing obat penis keluar nanah mengapa penis keluar nanah_11 obat penyakit kencing nanah atau gonore cairan nanah dari kemaluan obat denature sipilis pusat pengobatan herbal ada rasa gatal pada saluran kencing obat penyakit sipilis herbal sipilis dari denature
Obat kencing Nanah De Nature Obat Herbal obat Kutil Kelaminpengobatan penyakit herpes kelamin cara mengobati herpes kelamin obat herpes kelamin obat herpes kelamin
Post a Comment