In my latest Verdict column, I discuss the recent landmark ruling of the Supreme Court of India finding an implicit right to privacy in the Constitution of the world's largest democracy. My column is mostly laudatory. I also take the opportunity to discuss the virtues of comparative law. The Privacy Case judgment canvasses constitutional privacy jurisprudence in the UK, US, South Africa, Canada, and the EU. I suggest that we, in turn, could learn from sister legal systems.
In this essay, I want to address an issue that arises in passing in the Privacy Case: what is sometimes called "food freedom," i.e., the right to decide for oneself what to eat. The judgment does not discuss the issue at any length, but it does--unfortunately in my view--suggest that food freedom may be on the agenda for future cases. In a paragraph that mentions a variety of prior cases involving privacy issues, the court includes "food preferences and animal slaughter (Hinsa Virodhak Sangh)." The case cited is a 2008 judgment of a two-justice panel of the Indian Supreme Court rejecting a challenge to Ahmedabad ordinances closing municipal slaughterhouses during the eight-day Jain festival of Paryushan. As the panel saw it, that case involved the "right to carry on an occupation, trade or business" and the right to religious freedom or what we might call religious establishment in the US.
Properly understood, the Sangh case did not involve a right to food preference or food freedom. To the extent that the Indian Supreme Court has now implied that such a right may be protected in India under the rubric of a right to privacy, that implication should be rejected in future cases.
To be clear, there were real issues of religious liberty and anti-establishment in the Sangh case. Prime Minister Narendra Modi's BJP often promotes Hindu nationalism at the expense of the religious pluralism enshrined in India's constitution. At the time of the Sangh case, Modi was Chief Minister of Gujarat, where Ahmedabad is located. And while Jains represent less than four percent of the Ahmedabad population, their religious beliefs and practices--especially with respect to meat--are much closer to those of the Hindu majority than the Muslim minority who perceive anti-slaughter laws as targeting them. The Sangh panel rejected the religious discrimination claim chiefly because the justices saw the ordinance as an attempt at fostering mutual respect rather than coercion or proselytization. They cited the practice of the sixteenth century Mughal Emperor Akbar the Great, who, despite his own Muslim faith, which permits meat consumption, forbade animal slaughter during Paryushan. The court thus concluded that the relatively modest imposition on slaughterhouse operators and their customers was constitutionally valid.
Readers can decide for themselves whether they think the Sangh case was rightly or wrongly decided with respect to religious discrimination. The not-coercion-just-respect argument was used by our Supreme Court to uphold Sunday closing laws (which apply for 52 days each year, not just 8) against an establishment challenge in the McGowan case and against a free exercise challenge in the Braunfield case. So-called "blue laws" persist in many states, while the federal appeals courts have rejected challenges to state laws making Good Friday an official holiday. To my mind, all of these rulings are problematic, but the Sangh decision is not more problematic than similar US decisions.
In any event, even if one thinks that the Indian Supreme Court erred in Sangh, it does not follow that there is--as the nine-justice panel in The Privacy Case suggested--a right to "food preferences and animal slaughter" that properly falls within the umbrella of privacy. To analogize to a US case, as Justice Blackmun, joined by Justice O'Connor, emphasized in a concurrence in the Church of Lukumi case, although a law that forbids animal slaughter by targeting a particular religion may be invalid, a law that in purpose and effect aims at protecting animals from cruelty would stand on a different footing.
Justices Blackmun and O'Connor thus noted in Lukumi that the Court decision there did not entail a right to an exception from anti-cruelty laws for people engaging in otherwise-forbidden practices on religious grounds. Because they also thought that Employment Division v. Smith was wrongly decided, Justices Blackmun and O'Connor thought it an open question whether there would be a right to such an exception under the Free Exercise Clause. But with Smith still the governing law, the question today would be whether the Religious Freedom Restoration Act (RFRA) requires such exceptions to a federal anti-cruelty law or whether state RFRAs (or their equivalent) require such exceptions to state and local laws. The Blackmun/O'Connor Lukumi concurrence suggests that RFRA and RFRA-like regimes might not require exceptions to neutral anti-cruelty laws because there could be a compelling interest in preventing cruelty to animals sufficient to override the individual's right under RFRA and RFRA-like state laws. My own view (it will not surprise readers familiar with my work on animals to learn) is that such an interest is indeed compelling.
The compelling interest question arises where there is a prima facie right--as I acknowledge there could be where a claimant asserts a right to religious freedom that entitles her to partake of some particular food or to harm or kill an animal to make that food. But what about the broader suggestion by the Indian Supreme Court in the Privacy Case that there is a right to "food preference and animal slaughter" quite apart from any concerns about religious freedom or religious discrimination? To make the question concrete, suppose a liberal democracy in which the government enacts laws restricting which animals may be killed for food, how they may be killed for food, or even forbidding the killing of all animals for food--not because of any views about religion but because of a secular philosophical view that such practices are wrong in virtue of the harms they inflict upon animals. And suppose further that such laws are challenged by people who hold no religious views but simply want to eat cheeseburgers or ham and eggs for the culinary pleasure they derive from such foods. Does such a challenge implicate a right to privacy?
We can readily dispense with a threshold objection. Someone might say that the challenge does not involve a right to privacy because the food will be purchased and perhaps consumed in public. Put that objection aside because "privacy" as used in the case law in the US, India, and other constitutional democracies is often a term of art that encompasses aspects of liberty that find expression in public settings.
The challenge to the Affordable Care Act that culminated in NFIB v. Sebelius provides a useful illustration of how one kind of food freedom argument might go. The challengers--echoed by Chief Justice Roberts--fretted that if the federal government could use the Commerce Clause power to require people to purchase health insurance it could also use that same power to require people to eat broccoli. This was a doubly bad argument (as Justice Ginsburg noted). First, requiring people to buy broccoli is not the same as requiring them to eat it. And second, the objection that the government shouldn't require people to eat broccoli sounds in substantive due process, not federalism.
But if the government did require people to eat broccoli that would be a violation of the constitutional right to privacy, which encompasses a right to bodily integrity. If, as the SCOTUS assumed in the Cruzan case, a competent adult has a constitutional right to refuse all food even if it means starving to death, then it's a slam-dunk to say that there is a constitutional right to refuse any particular food when the immediate consequences are nowhere near as severe.
So yes, a properly understood liberal democratic constitution ought to contain a right to "food preferences" in the sense of a competent adult's right not to be forced by the government to consume any particular food. In other words, there is a negative food preference right.
However, it does not follow that there is a positive food preference right, i.e., a right to consume whatever food one likes. Numerous laws in the US and elsewhere barring particular food additives or foods produced in various ways on the grounds of health risks make this clear. Does anybody think that laws that aim to reduce the risk of foodborne illnesses (like listeria and salmonella) even raise constitutional issues on the ground that they limit people's ability to consume the food they might otherwise choose to consume?
One might think that health and safety laws are different from laws that aim at other sorts of goals. But that's simply not so. If you have a taste for endangered species, too bad. Even if you really would like to eat a bald eagle--which is no longer endangered--too bad. The federal Humane Methods of Slaughter Act is grossly under-inclusive and under-enforced, but it does limit the putative right to eat whatever you like.
Now I suppose one might think that all of these laws violate a basic right to food freedom, but that position has no logical stopping point and thus amounts to across-the-board libertarianism. A positive right to eat whatever you like (rather than to avoid being forced to eat what you don't like) is mighty hard to distinguish from a right to drive without a seatbelt, a right to fight to the death, a right to take unapproved (but in your judgment not especially dangerous) drugs, etc. Across-the-board libertarians may well support food freedom, but the basic principle of a constitutional right to privacy singles out particular aspects of liberty that are especially important or vulnerable for protection.
In Beating Hearts: Abortion and Animal Rights, Professor Colb and I say that we do not currently favor laws forbidding the consumption of animal products, even though we are vegans ourselves. However, we add that this view is strategic rather than a matter of principle:
Given current practices, there is no realistic chance of securing a legal prohibition on consuming animal products, and thus we think that advocacy efforts should focus chiefly on changing hearts and minds. In a future in which vegans constitute something like a majority of the population, we might reevaluate the wisdom of seeking legal prohibition. We reject the notion that individual consumers are entitled, as a matter of right, to consume animal products.Our view is not idiosyncratic. Absent an express (and in our view misguided) text granting an explicit right to food freedom, liberal constitutionalism does not entail it.
7 comments:
I do think reference to international practice and law can be useful and have seen various courts, including South Africa, find some value in our own experience. In neither case do foreign practice decide the law. It's informative.
Justice Tom Clark in his well cited abortion article noted:
"Unless the State has a compelling subordinating interest that outweighs the individual rights of human beings, it may not interfere with a person's marriage, home, children, and day to day living habits. This is one of the fundamental concepts that the Founding Fathers had in mind when they drafted the Constitution."
I think "day to day living habits" includes matters of diet. The discussion notes there is a right negatively here, such as refusing to eat broccoli. But, there is also rights there to do things like grow, buy and sell (such as a right to buy contraceptives). And, it is good policy for the government to help -- e.g., food stamps for those who need it.
The essay here seems a bit of a strawman: "a right to consume whatever food one likes." Well, rights are rarely absolute. Abortion is regulated. Speech is regulated etc. I think particularly given the religious aspects, there is some right to "food preference." As with other rights, it would be allowed to be regulated, including sale of impure food. As with a personal right to use drugs, I'm not sure just how pure consumption would be affected there. Would we have a law against adults drinking spoiled milk in their homes?
"Animal slaughter" would be problematic for a special reason given animals have rights or at least special interests. As long as we allow usage of animals badly, there very well might honestly be a "right" (depending on how you formulate that) to slaughter them, but even there a "right" would still allow regulation. Anyway, unfortunately for some, India accepts usage of animals, including for religious rituals, so I think it would be seen as a "right" unless the position of animals as a whole is changed. As seen for many groups in this country, this change is possible over time.
Under our own constitutional law, as of now, animals don't have the status some wish. So, if there is a right over food choices, it very well might involve consumption of animals. This still would be open to regulation such as Justice Blackmun noted in the animal sacrifice case. I don't believe Blackmun was a vegan. (Prof. Colb was involved in the writing of that opinion, as was noted here in the past).
There is a lot to digest here. I agree that an assertion of food preference/privacy shouldn't generally invalidate a law impacting/forbidding availability. Yet, I have some questions, at least some of which may be resolved by further consideration. Here are a couple of hypotheticals that come to mind initially:
If the government includes a requirement in the food stamps program that at least %20 must be spent on meat and 40% on vegetables (because the government deems it healthy) is that a violation of privacy rights?
Or what if the government decides to make everyone healthier by providing food vouchers for every American with a scheme of purchase requirements, penalties for a failure to adhere, and attendant substantial taxes (reducing potential to buy off-program). Does it matter whether such law forbids or requires the purchase of meat with the vouchers?
It may be that privacy rights are not directly implicated in these schemes - I'm not entirely sure - but I can't help but think that there are both positive and negative rights to food preferences impacted depending on how a law operates.
I think micromanaging food choices as part of a subsidy program can be problematic but the state can simply give out vouchers for specific types of foods and subsidize certain things (as they already do) to advance the same general ends of the hypo.
I think in practice it often will be a policy matter and more of a thought experiment. OTOH, one 1960s discussion of the right to privacy discussed poverty campaigns where there was pressure to use birth control and the like in government programs.
While Prof. Dorf is certainly right in an absolute sense that the right to food preference as a matter of religious freedom is different from a right to food preference as a privacy right, I suspect that in India the two are in some ways hopelessly intertwined, and it's likely that the court was thinking of food preference as something closer to a right to private exercise of your religion (or lack thereof) rather than an absolute right to eat whatever you want.
It may not be possible, with India's current religious culture, to pass a generally applicable law prohibiting animal slaughter that is not clearly religiously motivated.
P.S.: Joe is right, Prof. Dorf's argument eventually degrades into a somewhat ridiculous strawman. I don't actually believe that the panel of judges believe that the right to privacy necessarily implicates a right to eat EVERYTHING. Laws that individuals are not allowed to eat other people without their permission would not be construed by any reasonable court to violate the eater's right to privacy.
First, as far as your arguments from the permissibility of health, cruelty and other regulations goes, much the same is true of the abortion right; the state can regulate to prevent unhealthy forms of abortion or especially cruel forms of abortion (partial-birth). Does anyone think, you ask, that laws about salmonella even raise constitutional issues? No, but does anyone think requiring an abortionist to be a doctor or use sterilized equipment raises constitutional issues? Were there a right to choose food, some regulations would so easily pass muster that they wouldn't raise any serious issue.
Of course you're right that a right to privacy singles out important aspects of liberty. I guess it's not completely obvious to me, though, that choice of food is much less important than choice of sexual partner. People care quite deeply about food, and I would suggest that if you were to attempt to explain why sexual liberty is much more important than culinary liberty, whatever you would say would rest on one or more contested claims about sexuality that either sentimentalizes sex, a la Kennedy in Lawrence, in a way that many people don't recognize, or makes some ethical claim about sex that many people would reject. On the other hand, I think there's probably a pretty robust consensus that banning meat would at least be a substantially greater intrusion on liberty than seatbelt laws. Food is a universal biological need, the subject of intense likes and dislikes on the part of virtually everyone, the substance of family and religious traditions, a kind of art, the subject of a vast literature and thousands of passionate debates - I could go on for quite a while, but I don't have any real interest in making a case for food freedom, other than to say that it's a much closer question than seatbelt freedom.
Sr. Cashman, le doy las gracias por esta información. Friv Games Gry Friv Gry Friv n todo momento puede Friv Juegos Friv Friv Games optar por compartir su información personal con terceros. Juegos Friv Juegos Friv Friv 5 Friv 2018 Gracias por compartir su pasión por el mejoramiento de las vidas de los niños en el Estado de Nueva York
Louis Armstrong in his "Loveless Love" seems to be quizzicle about the need for a "Pure Food Law" suggesting that people expect food to be healthy. But the "free market" didn't necessarily agree, ergo the "Pure Food Law." [The song addresses certain inconsistencies that had been surfacing in 1920 America resulting in this variation on "Careless Love" which might get into sexual privacy discussed in this thread.]
Post a Comment