Thursday, August 07, 2008

Agreeing to Disagree: Credit Cards and Contract Absolutism

The Federal Reserve recently solicited comments from the public about problems in the credit card industry. Yesterday's lead editorial in The New York Times, "Listen to the 56,000," takes its title from the number of responses that poured into the Fed from the public, a torrent of complaints that covered a range of more-than-questionable industry policies, including “universal default,” which the Times describes as "the practice of raising interest rates on accounts in good standing when a borrower falls behind on other bills." The editors call upon Congress to step in with stronger protections against various abusive practices.

While I agree that better laws are needed, I have come to think that this is yet another area where we are so tied up in our own rhetoric that much-needed reform will fall victim to absolutist posturing. The problem is in our use of classical contract terminology to describe modern impersonal transactions. We all sign (or click through) a "cardholder agreement," which has the look and language of a formal contract. In most such documents, we (the cardholders) seem to be agreeing to all of the things that we are now complaining about. Moreover, even if some industry practices are not actually in the agreements that we signed, the typical contract allows the company to change its policies at any time and without notice. So what are we complaining about?! Suck it up, be a grown up, and live by our promises, right? This is ultimately the argument against helping people in danger of defaulting on mortgages as well. If the company is not actually committing fraud, anything that it does within the letter of the agreement is fair game.

Moreover, there is at least a plausible argument for each of these policies. Universal default, after all, can be defended by pointing out that a company will naturally view a loan as being at greater risk if the borrower is found to be in arrears elsewhere. Higher risk means higher rates. Even the foundational "unconscionability" case in the 1L Contracts class, Williams v. Walker-Thomas Furniture, describes a practice to which a well-informed borrower might agree in exchange for other consideration.

The problems with that basic assumption (that the two parties have agreed to the terms of the contract in the way that offer/acceptance logic presumes) are legion, and legal scholars have increasingly drawn on psychological theories to describe the cognitive limitations that lead us quite rationally to "agree" to things with which we would not agree. My purpose is not to rehash those arguments here but to point out that, as usual, the political debate will be about absolutes rather than line-drawing. Anything that Congress proposes as a consumer protection measure will be attacked as: (1) undermining freedom of contract and/or being paternalistic, and (2) ultimately harming those whom it purports to help. (The banks "warn of unintended consequences, mainly that less credit would be available to consumers.")

The only possible answer to #1 is that, yes, of course these laws will prevent some contract terms from being available that some parties might have agreed to in a face-to-face, hard-nosed negotiation; but we're making a policy decision to limit some of the options based on an assessment that the credit card contracting process doesn't look like the simplified world that even classical contract theorists like Williston understood a century ago to be over-stylized. As to #2, again, yes. Some credit really should not be extended to some consumers. This is not a surprise to anyone. In fact, reducing credit card indebtedness is, in other contexts, often held up as an important public policy goal.

"But they agreed!" Again, my argument is not that every credit card agreement should be invalidated or that Congress should adopt every policy proposal that might be gleaned from those 56,000 complaints. What it should do, though, is understand that we already live in a world where "agreements" are sometimes invalid or will not be recognized. Even though this is not a hot-button political issue in the category of taxes or terrorism, though, we can still expect that it will be sound-bitten beyond recognition. As is so often the case, I hope to be proven wrong.

-- Posted by Neil H. Buchanan

7 comments:

egarber said...

I wonder if some of the problem is structural. I'm reminded of the post a while back about fragmented ownership.

In much the same way as with mortgages, credit card debt is sold off onto the secondary market -- meaning there's incentive for credit card companies to cut corners on front-end creditworthiness. They no longer have skin in the game once the debt is resold, so what's the risk, really? I think that might account for over-extended credit in the first place.

Of course, it can reach a point (maybe it has?) where so many are in trouble that the fine print has to be invoked, basically pounding the very people who can least absorb it.

I guess my point is that spreading around risk encourages companies to be too loose in the first place. In the end, we'd be much better off if people were denied credit at the outset, if they pose that much risk.

On your post, I think you're right that the debate will get lost in absolutes.

Tam Ho said...

This post and Prof. Colb's post from yesterday focus (among other things) on a theme that I find interesting: the inapplicability of catchy-sounding inflexible "first principles" in light of empirical facts.

Thus, the theoretical argument against "discrimination" sounds like a great idea if we were creating the world anew, but loses its force when one considers the history of this country. Likewise, the "freedom to contract" argument against consumer protection sounds good until one realizes that often, there is no meaningful negotiation (and thus, no choice, or freedom - at least for the consumer) in these contract-of-adhesion situations anyway.

The approach of "starting from first principles" and then going from there, no matter what results it commits you to, probably has the appeal of appearing logically rigorous, fair, principled, etc. But in reality, it's just the same as the puerile game of "logical gotcha" that I used to play with my parents.

Upon their denying me permission to do something, I would corner my Mom or Dad (or both simultaneously, if possible - their increased numbers only made it easier for me to pick and choose statements to deconstruct) into asserting a principled reason for the prohibition, upon which point I would offer a counterexample precedent (e.g., of a past instance that fell on the same side of the asserted principle as the current situation, but where they granted me permission) or hypothetical that would break their principle, and then accuse them of inconsistency or arbitrariness, or of being ad-hoc if they revised their answer to account for the apparent inconsistency. They never actually changed their mind, but I always walked away with the perception of a moral victory.

What I didn't realize until later in life was that my cleverness hardly meant that they didn't have good reasons for their decisions. But due to the complexity of language and the world, it's just impossible to come up with a rigid set of principles that applies under all possible circumstances.

Unfortunately, as Prof. Buchanan notes, rigid, absolutist principles lend themselves far better to marketing and propaganda than do accurate explanations of the world. If only I knew back then that it was actually my parents who were scoring the moral victories for putting up with my sophistry.

Anonymous said...

免費A片, ut聊天室, AV女優, 美女視訊, 免費成人影片, 成人論壇, 情色交友, 免費AV, 線上a片, 日本美女寫真集, 同志聊天室, 聊天室交友, 成人文章, 成人圖片區, 色情網站, 辣妹視訊, 美女交友, 微風成人區, 色美媚部落格, 色情影片, 成人影片, 成人網站, 免費A片, 上班族聊天室, A片,H漫, 18成人, a漫, av dvd, 一夜情聊天室, 微風成人, 成人圖片, 成人漫畫, 情色網, 日本A片, 免費A片下載, 性愛, 成人交友, 嘟嘟成人網, 嘟嘟成人網, 成人貼圖, 成人電影, 成人, 中部人聊天室, 080中部人聊天室, 成人貼圖, 成人小說, 成人文章, 成人圖片區, 免費成人影片, 成人遊戲, 微風成人, 愛情公寓, 成人電影, A片, 情色, 情色貼圖, 情色文學, 做愛, 成人遊戲, 成人影城, 色情聊天室, 色情小說, 一葉情貼圖片區, 情色小說, 色情, 寄情築園小遊戲, 色情遊戲, 成人網站, 麗的色遊戲, 色情網站, 成人論壇, 情色視訊, 情色電影, aio交友愛情館, 言情小說, 愛情小說, 色情A片, 情色論壇, 自拍, 癡漢, , 俱樂部, 豆豆聊天室, 聊天室, 色情影片, 視訊聊天室, 免費視訊聊天, 免費視訊, 視訊交友90739 情人視訊網影音視訊聊天室 免費視訊聊天室 視訊聊天 視訊交友 美女視訊 視訊美女 視訊 免費視訊 免費視訊聊天 視訊聊天室 辣妹視訊 一夜情 色情a片 aio交友愛情館 情色電影 情色視訊 色情遊戲 色情 情色小說 一葉情貼圖片區 色情小說 色情聊天室 情色交友 成人論壇 成人網站 色情網站 情色論壇 小高聊天室 女同志聊天室 6K聊天室 080苗栗人聊天室 080聊天室 聊天室尋夢園 UT男同志聊天室 男同志聊天室 尋夢園聊天室 UT聊天室 聊天室 豆豆聊天室 A片 成人電影 成人貼圖 嘟嘟成人網 美女交友 本土自拍 成人交友 成人影片http://ssff01.3b8mm.com/

Anonymous said...

I always heard something from my neighbor that he sometimes goes to the internet bar to play the game which will use him some habbo credits,he usually can win a lot of habbo gold,then he let his friends all have some habbo coins,his friends thank him very much for introducing them the cheap habbo credits,they usually buy habbo gold together.

Anonymous said...

酒店喝酒,禮服店,酒店小姐,酒店經紀,制服店,便服店,鋼琴酒吧,兼差,酒店兼差,酒店打工,伴唱小姐,暑假打工,酒店上班,日式酒店,舞廳,ktv酒店,酒店,酒店公關,酒店小姐,理容院,日領,龍亨,學生兼差,酒店兼差,酒店上班,酒店打工,禮服酒店,禮服店 ,酒店小姐,酒店兼差,寒暑假打工,酒店小姐,台北酒店,禮服店 ,酒店小姐,酒店經紀,酒店兼差,寒暑假打工,酒店小姐,台北酒店,禮服店 ,酒店小姐,酒店經紀,酒店兼差,寒暑假打工,酒店小姐,台北酒店,禮服店 ,酒店小姐,酒店經紀,酒店兼差,寒暑假打工,酒店小姐,台北酒店,禮服店 ,酒店小姐,酒店經紀,酒店兼差,寒暑假打工,酒店小姐,台北酒店,禮服店 ,酒店小姐,酒店兼差,寒暑假打工,酒店小姐,台北酒店,禮服店 ,酒店小姐,酒店經紀,酒店兼差,寒暑假打工,酒店小姐,台北酒店,禮服店 ,酒店小姐,酒店經紀,酒店兼差,打工,酒店小姐,台北酒店,禮服店 ,酒店小姐,酒店經紀,酒店兼差,寒暑假打工,酒店小姐,台北酒店,禮服店 ,酒店小姐,酒店經紀,酒店兼差,寒暑假打工,酒店小姐,禮服店 ,酒店小姐,酒店經紀,酒店兼差,寒暑假打工,酒店小姐,禮服店 ,酒店小姐,酒店經紀,酒店兼差,寒暑假打工,酒店小姐,禮服店 ,酒店小姐,酒店經紀,酒店兼差,寒暑假打工,酒店小姐,禮服店 ,酒店小姐,酒店經紀,酒店兼差,寒暑假打工,酒店小姐,禮服店 ,酒店小姐,酒店經紀,酒店兼差,寒暑假打工,酒店小姐,經紀 彩色爆米花,經紀人 彩色爆米花,酒店傳播,酒店經紀 彩色爆米花,爆米花,童裝,童裝拍賣,童裝大盤,童裝寄賣,童裝批貨,酒店,酒店,童裝切貨,酒店,GAP童裝,酒店,酒店 ,禮服店 , 酒店小姐,酒店經紀,酒店兼差,寒暑假打工

Anonymous said...

,,姐.,便服/,,

Anonymous said...

酒店經紀人, 菲梵酒店經紀, 酒店經紀, 禮服酒店上班, 酒店小姐兼職, 便服酒店經紀, 酒店打工經紀, 制服酒店工作, 專業酒店經紀, 合法酒店經紀, 酒店暑假打工, 酒店寒假打工, 酒店經紀人, 菲梵酒店經紀, 酒店經紀, 禮服酒店上班, 酒店經紀人, 菲梵酒店經紀, 酒店經紀, 禮服酒店上班, 酒店小姐兼職, 便服酒店工作, 酒店打工經紀, 制服酒店經紀, 專業酒店經紀, 合法酒店經紀, 酒店暑假打工, 酒店寒假打工, 酒店經紀人, 菲梵酒店經紀, 酒店經紀, 禮服酒店上班, 酒店小姐兼職, 便服酒店工作, 酒店打工經紀, 制服酒店經紀,,